The Resurrection of Jesus:
A Rational Inquiry
Habermas: Dissertationby Gary Robert Habermas

A Dissertation Submitted to
Michigan State University, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, Interdisciplinary Studies, College of Arts and Letters, 1976.
 
This is an electronic copy of the entire Dissertation. Some things have been changed from the original, including:
  • Footnotes changed to endnotes.
  • Special characters changed to English equivalents.
  • Horizontal Rules indicate original pagination points.
     
Special thanks to Jon-Marc Costanza for his invaluable assistance in preparing this HTML version of the dissertation.
 

We apologize for the typos present in this version. They do not exist in the original.
(available without typos as a scanned PDF here).

page i

 

 

ABSTRACT

THE RESURRECTION OF JESUS: A RATIONAL INQUIRY

By

Gary Robert Habermas

The subject of this dissertation is the resurrection of Jesus, which is perceived to be the central doctrine of the Christian faith. The subject is treated rationally in regards to the possibility of the resurrection being a historical event.

Research in this topic falls into the realms of three disciples--religion, history and philosophy. The entire question is admittedly most related to Christian theology, but there has also been an upsurge in the amount of interest from contemporary history and philosophy as well. Some of these trends in intellectual thought are also investigated.

This dissertation therefore deals with the problems encountered in a rational approach to the resurrection. As stated above, the main purpose is to endeavor to ascertain if this occurrence can be demonstrated to be historical or not. However, there are other definite implications involved beyond this immediate purpose, for if the resurrection actually happened (or if it did not) this is surely much significance for Christian faith and theology.

The method used is first to investigate some preliminary questions. After studying the importance of the resurrection in contemporary intellectual thought (especially in these three disciplines), the relation of this even (as a claimed miracle) to science an history is examined. Also included is a study of the philosophical problem of reason and faith.

The main format consists of an investigation of three possible intellectual approaches to the resurrection. The first possibility is that this even did not occur literally at all. The second possibility is that it did occur, but that it cannot be demonstrated as such. The third possibility is that the resurrection did occur literally and that it can be demonstrated. It is extremely important to note here that the word "demonstrate" is not used as a synonym for "absolute proof" in this study. To belief that the resurrection can be demonstrated is this a reference to probabilities--that the resurrection is the most probably conclusion in light of the factual evidence.

The view of one primary scholar from each of three categories will be investigated, supplemented by several others who take a similar position regarding the occurrence of this event. One historian (David Hume), one philosopher (Soren Kierkegaard) and one theologian (Wolfhart Pannenberg) are the primary scholars. It is not the overall philosophies of these scholars which are studied, but rather their approach to this occurrence.

Lastly, an evaluation of each of these three possibilities is given. The object here is to ascertain the approach which is best supported by the facts.

The major findings of this study are difficult to summarize briefly because the argument here is a closely-knit one. However, it is concluded first that science and history cannot rule out the miraculous with an investigation. A priori rejections are not possible in view of the modern concepts of science and history. In addition, it is found that an investigation of the facts is needed in order to ascertain if miracles such as the resurrection actually occurred or not. An inductive study of the facts based upon the probability of the findings is thus the proper procedure and the one used here.

The results show that the literal resurrection of Jesus is in all probability a historical fact. Alternate theories are thoroughly investigated as part of the three major possibilities outlined above. It is found that there are no naturalistic views which adequately explain the facts. In addition, there are several strong historical facts which also point to this even. Based upon such probabilities, the resurrection is affirmed as a historical even. There are also certain implications for Christian faith and theology because of this conclusion.


page ii

 

To

DEBBIE

My love, my closest earthly friend and my wife,
whose own love for me was revealed even more by
her diligence in typing this dissertation.

 

 

  


page iii

 

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

From Lessing's Theological Writings by Gotthold E. Lessing, edited by Henry Chadwick. Copyright 1956 by Adam and Charles Black Ltd. Used by permission.

From The Essential Works of David Hume by David Hume, edited by Ralph Cohen. Copyright 1965 by Bantum Books, Inc.

From The Suicide of Christian Theology by John Warwick Montgomery, published and copyright 1970 by Bethany Fellowship, Inc., Minneapolis, Minnesota 55438. Reprinted by permission.

From Where is History Going by John Warwick Montgomery, published by Bethany Fellowship, Inc., Minneapolis, Minnesota 55438. Copyright (c) 1969 Zondervan Publishing House, assigned to John Warwick Montgomery, 1972. Reprinted by permission.

From Theology, Physics and Miracles by Warner Schaaffs, translated by Richard L. Renfield. Copyright 1974 by Canon Press, distributed by Baker Book House. Used by permission.

From Christ the Center by Dietrich Bonhoeffer, translated by John Bowden. Copyright 1966 by Harper and Row, Publishers. Used by permission.

From Jesus of Nazareth by Gunther Bornkamm, translated by Irene and Frazer McLuskey with James M. Robinson. Copyright 1960 by Harper and Row, Publishers. Used by permission.

 


page iv

 

From "New Testament and Mythology" by Rudolf Bultmann, In Kerygma and Myth, edited by Hans Werner Bartsch, translated by Reginald H. Fuller. Copyright 1961 by Harper and Row, Publishers. Used by Permission.

From Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone by Immanuel Kant, translated by Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt H, Hudson. Copyright 1960 by Harper and Row, Publishers. Used by permission.

From The Word of God and the Word of Man by Karl Barth, translated Douglas Horton. Harper and Brothers. Copyright 1956, 1957 by Douglas Horton. Used by permission.

From The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, edited by William Morris. Copyright (c) 1969, 1970, 1971, 1973, 1975, 1976 by the Houghton Mifflin Company. Reprinted by permission.

From History and Christianity by John Warwick Montgomery. Copyright (c) 1964, 1965 by Inter-Varsity Christian Fellowship. Used by permission of Inter-Varsity Press, Downer's Grove, Illinois 60515.

From Your Mind Matters by John R.W. Stott. Copyright (c) 1972 by Inter-Varsity Press, London. Used by permission of Inter-Varsity Press, Downer's Grove, Illinois 60515.

From Christianity: A Historical Religion? by William Wand. Copyright 1972 by the Judson Press. Used by permission.

From the Revised Standard Version of the Bible. Copyright 1945, 1952, (c) 1971, 1973 by the National Council of the Churches of Christ.

From The Epistle to the Romans by Karl Barth, translated by Edwyn C. Hoskyns. Copyright 1933 by Oxford University Press. Used by permission.


page v

 

From Concluding Unscientific Postscript by Soren Kierkegaard, translated by David R. Swenson and Walter Lowrie. Copyright 1941 (c) 1969 Princeton University Press: Princeton Paperback, 1968. Published for the American Scandinavian Foundation. Reprinted by permission of Princeton University Press.

From Faith and History Reinhold Niebuhr. Copyright 1949 by Charles Scribner's Sons. Used by permission.

From The Doctrine of Reconciliation Volume IV, Part One of Church Dogmatics Karl Barth, edited by G.W. Bromily and T.F. Torrence. Copyright 1956 by T. and T. Clark.

From Jesus--God and Man by Wolfhart Pannenberg, translated by Lewis L. Wilkens and Duane A. Priebe. Copyright (c) 1968 by The Westminster Press. Used by permission.

From New Directions in Theology Today Volume II, History and Hermeneutics by Carl E. Braaten. The Westminster Press. Copyright (c) 1960 by W. L. Jenkins. Used by permission.

From Theology and the Kingdom of God by Wolfhart Pannenberg. Copyright (c) 1969 by the Westminster Press. Used by permission.

From Science Returns to God by James Jauncey. Copyright (c) 1961 by Zondervan Publishing House. Used by permission.

NOTE: The books listed here in the acknowledgments have been quoted from in this work and are used by permission.


pages vi - viii

 

TABLE OF CONTENTS

PART 1: APPROACHING THE QUESTION OF THE RESURRECTION OF JESUS

  • Chapter I. The Present State of the Question (p. 2)
    • A. Theology and the Resurrection (p. 4)
      • 1. The Importance of the Resurrection (p. 4)
      • 2. The Contemporary Theological Approach to the Resurrection (p.9)
    • B. History, Philosophy and the Resurrection (p. 12)
      • 1. History and the resurrection (p. 12)
      • 2. Philosophy and the Resurrection (p. 17)
  • Chapter II. The Possibility of Miracles Today (p. 26)
    • A. Miracle and Myth (p. 26)
      • 1. A Definition of Miracle (p. 26)
      • 2. A Definition of Myth (p. 29)
    • B. Twentieth Century Science and Miracles (p. 35)
      • 1. Introduction (p. 35)
      • 2. Some Principles of Physics (p. 39)
      • 3. Miracles (p. 43)
  • Chapter III. History and Miracles (p. 49)
    • A. A Concept of History (p. 49)
      • 1. Historical Research and Investigation (p. 54)
      • 2. The Resurrection and Historical Investigation (p. 58)
  • Chapter IV. Reason and Faith (p. 60)
    • A. Reason and Faith: Definitions (p. 61)
    • B. Reason and Faith: Scholarly Views (p. 66)

Part 2: POSSIBLE SOLUTIONS TO THE QUESTION OF THE RESURRECTION OF JESUS

  • Chapter V. Possibility Number One: That the Resurrection Did Not Occur (p. 82)
    • A. David Hume: An Introduction (p. 82)
    • B. David Hume's Argument and a Critique (p. 86)
  • Chapter VI. Possibility Number One: Other Similar Views (p. 114)
    • A. Heinrich Paulus (p. 119)
    • B. David Strauss (p. 127)
    • C. Otto Pfleiderer (p. 146)
  • Chapter VII. Possibility Number Two: That the Resurrection Did Occur, But that It Cannot Be Demonstrated (p. 172)
    • A. Soren Kierkegaard: An Introduction (p. 172)
    • B. Soren Kierkegaard's Argument and a Critique (p. 177)
  • Chapter VIII. Possibility Number Two: Other Similar Views (p. 198)
    • A. Karl Barth (p. 198)
    • B. Other Related Views (p. 218)
  • Chapter IX. Possibility Number Three: That the Resurrection Did Occur and That It Can Be Demonstrated (p. 225)
    • A. Wolfhart Pannenberg: An Introduction (p. 225)
    • B. Wolfhart Pannenberg's Argument and a Critique (p. 228)
  • Chapter X. Possibility Number Three: Other Similar Views (p. 260)

Part 3: AN EVALUTION OF THE SOLUTIONS TO THE QUESTION OF THE RESURRECTION OF JESUS

  • Chapter XI. An Evaluation of Possibility Number One (p. 286)
  • Chapter XII. An Evaluation of Possibility Number Two (p. 300)
  • Chapter XIII. An Evaluation of Possibility Number Three (p. 307)
  • Chapter XIV. A Concluding Demonstration (p. 312)
    • A. The Historical Method (p. 312)
    • B. The Historical Facts (p. 314)
    • C. The Theological Method (p. 323)
    • D. Convinced by the Facts (p. 326)
    • E. The Center of Christianity (p. 331)
  • Bibliography (p. 334)
  • Index of Persons (p. 347)
  • End Notes


page 1
 

PART 1

APPROACHING THE QUESTION OF THE

RESURRECTION OF JESUS

 


2

Chapter I. The Present State of the Question

The belief in the resurrection of Jesus has raised many questions and provoked much thought throughout the history of the Christian church. Is such as even possible and in what sense, if any? Can it still be believed in today or not? This "question of the resurrection" has received an increased amount of attention, especially in recent years. One quite surprising fact is that the discussion surrounding this topic is no longer relegated just to the field of religion alone, as various scholars from other disciplines have also shown some interest.

No one doubts that such inquiry falls primarily into the field of theology. Therefore we will turn here first in order to view generally the present state of the question of Jesus' resurrection. Later we will also deal briefly with the interest in the topic shown in two other areas--history and philosophy. The purpose of this chapter is primarily to note some present trends related to this question, keying on its importance for the Christian faith.

For the purposes of this paper, the resurrection will initially and briefly by defined in the terms of the New Testament concept. This even this refers to the Christian belief that Jesus was actually dead but later was literally raised to life by God. Jesus was believed to have appeared afterwards to his followers in a spiritually body, which was neither an unchanged physical body or a spirit. Rather, there were body objective and subjective qualities in this spiritual body. The Christian concept of resurrection therefore differs from other ideas concerning immortality in that Jesus was not reincarnated, neither did he simply experience the

 


3

continuance of his personality beyond the grave, nor was his soul absorbed into some type of universal soul. To the contrary, Jesus was believed to have literally been raised from the dead, as he appeared to his followers before his return to heaven. It is this Christian belief in Jesus' resurrection which must be investigated here. This definition will continue to broaden as this work expands.

Just before we turn to our first section certain cautions are in order. Because we are endeavoring to look at both sides of the argument and consider views that are "pro" and "con", we must take as little as possible for granted at the outset. For this reason we will refrain in almost all instances from capitalizing pronouns for Jesus, lest we begin to decide the question in advance. Concerning the use of such words as "this event" or "this occurrence" when referring to the resurrection, we do not mean to imply that we have already decided that it has happened. Rather, these words refer to what the New Testament claims has happened. Whether it actually did or not must yet by determined. Indeed, many theologians also refer to the resurrection as an even and still mean that it happened in other than a literal way. These words, then, must not always refer to something literal and often do not, as we shall see. In these ways the issue will hopefully not be prejudiced ahead of time.

  


4

A. Theology and the Resurrection

1. The Importance of the Resurrection

Many theologians today consider the resurrection of Jesus to be the central claim of Christianity, whether they interpret this event literally or not. Such was often true of past theologians as well. In other words, even those who do not affirm the post-mortem bodily appearances but sometimes stress instead the "spiritual presence" or continuing influence" of Jesus often feel that the resurrection is still the basis of the Christian faith.

For instance, German redaction critic Willi Marxsen believes that Jesus' resurrection plays the most decisive part of theological discussion today. This scholar feels that its importance was precisely stated by the apostle Paul in the first century A.D. when he write "if Christ has not been raised, then our preaching is in vain and your faith is in vain" (Cor. 15:14, RSV). For Marxsen this even is therefore linked with the very faith of the church. An uncertainty about questions such as those raised about might cause a corresponding uncertainty in our faith today.[1]

Another German theologian, Gunther Bornkamm, agrees with the ultimate importance of the resurrection, even if it may be impossible to grasp exactly what took place. He remarks that:

…there would be no gospel, not one account, no letter in the New Testament, no faith, no Church, no worship, no prayer in Christendom to this day without the message of the resurrection of Christ…[2]

  


5

Thus we see that for these two critical scholars, theological discussion and even theology itself finds its central aspect in the resurrection. This of course does not solve the problem or whether this even occurred or not and in what sense, as this must be given future consideration. Indeed, both Marxsen and Bornkamm do not believe we can prove it, but only affirm it by faith.[3] However, such statements do help serve to demonstrate how important a place in the Christian faith it is given by many, and that is the primary object of this chapter.

Other scholars also verify these convictions. For instance, Laurence Miller likewise believers that the resurrection of Jesus is the very heart of New Testament theology. Like Marxsen, he finds the definitive statement of this belief in Paul (I Cor. 15:12-22).[4] Merrill Tenney prefers to use the resurrection as a framework from all o f Christian theology, even dealing with some of the doctrines that can be integrated under theme.[5] Charles Anderson, in a section devoted entirely to the importance of the resurrection, also speaks of some of the Christian doctrines that are explained in the New Testament on the basis of this even. Again I Cor. 15:14 is

 


6

used as the key.[6]

Closely related views are held by other theologians as well. The former Anglican Archbishop of Canterbury, A.M. Ramsey, believes that the resurrection is not only the center of theology, but that it is also the starting place for studies revolving around the New Testament and its meaning.[7] For Daniel Fuller the resurrection is the basis of redemptive history. Events such as the cross receive much the belief in a risen Jesus.[8] C.C. Dobson asserts that even those who oppose all account of the resurrection still admit its importance as the keystone of Christianity.[9]

Every one in awhile a thesis such as the importance of the resurrection for the Christian faith will receive a new "twist", further demonstrating its relevance. This was achieved in recent years by Markus Barth and Verne H. Fletcher, who postulated that Jesus' resurrection was also the basis for Christian ethics. This event was perceived to have definite implications as a foundation human virtue and justice. In spite of its being a little-recognized theme, the authors believe that it is as relevant for us


7

today in these matters as it is in a strictly theological context.[10]

Even though many of the theologians above differ in other aspects of Christian belief, they all perceive that the resurrection is the center of theology even today. To be sure, they come from differing backgrounds, but they are all in agreement with Paul that if this event was to be completely abrogated, the Christian faith would be in jeopardy. As Marxsen states, if there is uncertainty or obscurity in the matter of belief in the resurrection, then Christianity becomes endangered. This demonstrates its importance as the center of theology today.[11]

Before leaving the subject of the importance of Jesus' resurrection, it should be mentioned that it is not only integral part of today's theology. In New Testament times it was also the doctrine upon which the Christian faith was built. We have already discussed Paul's statement to this effect above, where he states "if Christ has not been raised, then our preaching is in vain and your faith is in vain" (! Cor. 15:14, RSV. CF. verses 12-20). It was Paul's opinion that the resurrection of Jesus and the Christian faith stood or fell together. A stronger statement establishing the priority and importance of this occurrence for first century Christianity could hardly be established.

Recent theological studies have recognized this importance for the early church. Eminent New Testament scholar Rudolf Bultmann, while not personally accepting any sort of literal resurrection of


8

Jesus, still states that for the earliest Christians this event served the purpose of proving that God had substantiated the claims of Jesus by raising him from the dead.[12] The early Christians also believed that the resurrection proved Jesus' Lordship,[13] his Messiahship[14] and even that he was the Son of God.[15] According to the New Testament the resurrection also establishes the Christian doctrines of repentance,[16] salvation and justification by faith,[17] and judgment.[18] James McLeman has pointed out that early Christianity also witnesses to the belief that God began new dealing with mankind through the risen Jesus.[19]

Now we must be quick to point out once again that these beliefs by no means establish the fact of the resurrection. All we have demonstrated is that it is the center of Christian theology both in New Testament times and today. But this does not make it a proven


9

fact. The importance of an event does not, of course, establish whether it has actually occurred or not.

2. The Contemporary Theological Approach to the Resurrection

Perhaps the primary approach to the theological study of the resurrection today from a critical viewpoint is the application of the literary methods of form criticism and the related discipline, redaction criticism to the New Testament texts.[20] Two key works done on the resurrection from this standpoint are those by Willi Marxsen[21] and Reginald H. Fuller.[22]

According to Norman Perrin, the theological application of form critical literary techniques was insinuated in the work of Julius Wellhausen (1844-1918) and an early form of redaction criticism was first applied to theology in the writings of Wilhelm Wrede (1859-1906). After the First World War these studies were rejuvenated. Instead of a few theologians simply suggesting the form critical literary approach to Scripture studies, it became the common interest and a major emphasis of such scholars as K.L. Schmidt (1891-1956), Martin Dibelius (1883-1947) and Rudolf

 


10

Bultmann (born 1884).[23] Bultmann is probably the one who is best known for popularizing form criticism, applying it especially to the synoptic gospels and publishing the results in such essays as "The Study of the Synoptic Gospels".[24]

Briefly, according to this theory of interpretation, the synoptic gospels were the products of the faith of the earliest first century Christian church. In other words, after years of orally spreading the gospel of Jesus Christ (and perhaps also by some written records which we no longer have, such as the Quelle document), the earliest church decided to write down what it could recall of the life of Jesus. But since the first Christians were not given a complete historical narrative of his life, their recollections could only be of independent occurrences. The gospels, then, can be broken down into these separate occurrences which in turn correspond to certain forms. When all of these occurrences are divided up into these forms, Bultmann notes that we have several classifications such as miracle stories, parables and apocalyptic words.[25]

Since the church was interested in a complete biography, however, these events had to be connected into a day by day account of Jesus' life. One can find a good many of these editorial links that tie one story to another. This is how the likeness to "beads on a string" has come to be used for the form critical approach. A main object

 


11

for theologians who employ this approach is to ascertain which of the account (or parts of account) in the gospels are actually historical stories and which were "constructed" by the faith of the early church.[26]

Redaction criticism relies heavily on the procedures of form criticism and builds upon its premises. In fact, Perrin notes that these may be seen as being two stages of the same discipline.[27]

Redaction criticism has developed significantly since the work done be Wilhelm Wrede at the end of the nineteenth and beginning of the twentieth centuries. Today more positive attention is given to the gospel authors, as they are seen as having more of a integral and original role to play in the choosing of material and in the written portrayal of it. Critics today also feel that a primary goal is to be able to trace the material through the various phrases of influence, through the various additions by redactors and then as closely as possible to the source (s). This will enable them to determine, among other things, where the facts originated and what is at the basis of the reports. The object is, or course, to ascertain the reliability of the data as much as possible, to see what is historical and what has been added to the original facts.[28]

Three of the leading redaction critics today, at least in a chronological sense, are Gunther Bornkamm,[29] Hans Conzelmann and Willi Marxsen.[30] They worked independently on the synoptic gospels

 


12

of Matthew, Luke and Mark, respectively. In a sense they have paved the way for similar studies today.[31]

We have briefly investigated form and redaction criticism for two main reasons. First, its importance as the currently accepted literary approach to Biblical studies should not be underrated. We have noted about that same entire works and portions of others have been devoted to studies on the resurrection by scholars who favor these two disciplines.[32] Thus form and redaction criticism will provide a basis for much of what will be said hereafter. Second, although this writer does not embrace many of the facets and conclusions of either form criticism and redaction criticism, we will adopt many of its procedures here as the most commonly accepted "rules of the trade". With this background and theological foundation, it is advantageous to proceed now to two other fields of study which have also given recent attention to the subject of the resurrection.

B. History, Philosophy an the Resurrection

We have already stated that one interesting aspect of current study on the resurrection of Jesus is that several scholars in other fields of study besides religion have also become interested in


13

this question. These men have applied their various inter-disciplinary background and educations to the problem and have understandably came to various conclusions. Although these trends are probably most observable in the disciplines of history and philosophy, they are no means confined to these two areas. Other scholars (and their fields) who have shown as interest in this event included C.S. Lewis, the late Cambridge University professor of English literature,[33] J.N.D. Anderson, a lawyer and the University of London's director of advanced Legal Studies,[34] Peter L. Berger, Professor of Sociology at Rutgers University,[35] Louis Cassels, journalist and late columnist for United Press International[36] and scientist Henry Morris.[37] Let us turn now specifically to the fields of history and philosophy to observe some of the current interest in the question of the resurrection.

1. History and the Resurrection

It is true that most modern historians do not show an extraordinary amount of interest in the resurrection. Neither are they

 


14

usually concerned over whether it was a historical event or not. Generally the attitude taken in historical works towards this occurrence is one either of skepticism[38] or one that relates the Biblical accounts to the death and resurrection of Jesus only after a short preface what states "the Bible claims…", or "early Christians believed that…", or another similar expression.[39] This general non-interest in the resurrection by historians is understandable in view of the fact that many feel that this event is an item of faith, even if they believe that it actually occurred.

Yet there are some historians who have investigated this event to some extent. It is not our purpose here in this chapter to cover all areas of historical inquiry, but rather to briefly survey a sample of a few historians who have shown interest in the subject of the resurrection. Later the position of historian David Hume will be discussed in much more detail, as his views were extremely influential on the question of miracles.

Ancient historian Paul Maier has recently published a book entitled First Easter..[40] This work is concerned to a large extent with the first Easter Sunday and the question "What did happen at dawn on Sunday morning?"[41] His purpose is to try and

 


15

ascertain if history can tell us what really happened that day.[42] His method is first to investigate the original sources, comparing the various accounts of the early church which claim that Jesus rose from the dead. Alternate theories are then proposed and examined. Lastly, some interesting but seldom mentioned historical evidence that bears directly on this issue in studied.[43]

Maier has also contributed other scholarly articles concerning the death and resurrection of Jesus.[44] One entitled "The Empty Tomb as History", further examines the historical facts surrounding this event.[45] The conclusion to the article is concerned with whether or not the resurrection can be said to be a actual datum of history.[46] We will return to some of Maier's conclusions later.

Another ancient historian Edwin Yamauchi, has also written of the resurrection. His investigation is found in the two-part article entitled "Easter--Myth, Hallucination or History?"[47] He explores carefully each of the possibilities names in the title--the resurrection seen as an ancient myth, as an hallucination and as actual history. Yamauchi concludes first that the Christians concept of Jesus' resurrection could not have been derived from the myths ancient cultures such as those of the Sumerians, Babylonians or Egyptians, which appear to espouse belief in dying and rising


16

vegetation gods. These latter myths reveal both far to superficial resemblances and even very questionable evidence concerning this belief in a "resurrection" to have been the basis of belief for Jesus' rising.[48]

Yamauchi's second conclusion is that the hypothesis of hallucination is likewise not a strong enough impetus for belief in the resurrection of Jesus. None of the needed psychological prerequisites for visions are found in the New Testament accounts. For instance, the disciples were very despondent at the death of Jesus and failed to believe even after perceiving that he had risen, whereas hallucinations occur when individuals imagine beforehand that a certain thing has, in fact, happened. Visions are produced when people think so positively that they actually visualize what they desire after Jesus' death. The facts simple do not provide support for this theory at all. He conditions needed for hallucinations were plainly lacking.[49]

The final conclusion reached by Yamauchi is that the resurrection of Jesus is a historical even and must be dealt with as such. It simply cannot be termed as an existential occurrence and neither can it be forgotten about as a simply myth or delusion.[50]

We will at this point just quickly mention two other scholars in this field who also have dealt with the resurrection in their works. Historian and theologian John Warwick Montgomery has dealt


17

with this question in several works which are directly concerned with historical methodology.[51] Church historian William Wand has also fit the resurrection into an explicit historical framework.[52] Rather than explore the views of these two men at this point, we will return to them much more fully in the chapter on history and miracles. Suffice it to say at this time that while historians as a whole have not been overly concerned with Jesus' resurrection, it has been dealt with be several in this field. Thus it is the opinion of these scholars (and others) that this question is a historical one, to be decided by historical inquiry. Maier,[53] Yamauchi,[54] Montgomery.[55] and Wand[56] all agree that the question of the occurrence of the resurrection should be decided by the historical process of carefully weighing the evidence both for and against this event before a decision is made.

2. Philosophy and the Resurrection

As with most of the historians, so we also find that most contemporary philosophers are not often concerned with the question of Jesus' resurrection. But we find that several of these scholars


18

have also dealt with it as a part of their system of thought. As with the theologians, these philosophers offer a variety of approaches and answers to this event. Similar to the preceding short section on history, it is not our object in this chapter to treat every field of philosophy. To the contrary, the purpose here is simple to present a sample of a few philosophers who have dealt with the resurrection in their works. Later the positions of David Hume and Soren Kierkegaard will be examined in depth. Hume especially is recognized even by conservative theologians as offering a challenge to the belief in a literal resurrection and Kierkegaard also develops a popular philosophical view of this event. But at present it is our desire only to state the interest shown by a few philosophers of various intellectual inclinations.

Probably the best known philosopher who has investigated this occurrence is John Hick. In this essay "Theology and Verification"[57] he approaches the ancient topic of the possibility of verifying the existence of God. This is done in an interesting and novel (if somewhat questionable) manner.

For Hick, one cannot prove God's existence beyond any doubt. However, the author believes that one can reason logically to the probability of God's existence by the use of what he terms "eschatological" (or future) verification.[58]

The Christian faith (and various others as well) teach the reality of like after death. For Hick this concept of continued


19

survival is one which will ultimately be verified after death. In other words, the future resurrection of mankind can be verified experientially by each individual after his own personal death. The post-mortem knowledge one gains would prove that life does survive death.[59]

Concerning this odd-sounding apologetic for life after death, Hick attempts to explain how this is possible by the introduction of several interesting illustrations.[60] He feels that ultimately the question of immortality may be likened to two men walking down the road of life. One says that there is life after death at the end of the road, the other disagrees. But for them it is an experiential question. Sooner or later they will each turn the last bend in life and die. Then one will have been proven right and one wrong. This is eschatological verification of immortality.[61]

Even verification of the existence of God is to be found by the same future experience. Here Hick appropriates the role that Jesus plays. As we experience the risen Jesus and his reign in the Kingdom of God, and finally receive eschatological corroboration for this, we then also receive indirect verification of God. Thus the individual's own resurrection is the ultimate, experiential proof both of life after death and of God's existence. These truths are thus perceived as realities. Everyone will eventually prove the validity of these facts for themselves, however, because all will achieve this salvation and subsequent state of verification.[62]


20

Unfortunately, Hick's perception of the ability of one's own resurrection to verify such key tenets of theology raises more questions than it answers. It is interesting, to say the least, but it fails to logically reason out (and even presupposes) too many beliefs such as life after death and the ability to verify something such as God's existence even if the first was proven to be true.[63] Hick realizes that his hypotheses and those of Ian Crombie who also accepts eschatological verification, have both been met by disapproval from other philosophers and from theologians, but still feels that this is the best alternative in establishing the truth of theism.[34] Thus, while we must conclude that none of these doctrines can really be proven in this way, it does show the interest of a certain segment of philosophy in the question of the resurrection.

But it is not only in the writings of Hick (and those who agree with him) that we find an interest in the subject of the resurrection. The recent popularity of process thought has apparently opened up a new area of interest in the formulating, among other things, of a Christology based on process philosophy. For instance, Schubert Ogden's prospects for the development of a new Theism have led him to a reinterpretation of the resurrection based on the love of God.[65]


21

Another example is Bernard Loomer's attempt to explain the Christian faith, including the resurrection, in terms or process philosophy.[66]

In the work Process Philosophy and Christian Thought, Peter Hamilton proposes a modern Christology with a special emphasis upon the resurrection. For Hamilton, process philosophy offers the proper framework within which one can more properly view and formulate theology. This philosophy is perceived to be especially helpful in dealing with the resurrection.[67]

The key term that Hamilton adopts from process philosophy here is "immanence", which refers to the possibility of one reality being immanent or dwelt by another. This is illustrated by the way we often refer to the experiences of one individual "living on" in another's memory.[68]

When applied to the relationship between God and the world, immanence of a reference both to God's indwelling mankind and mankind's indwelling God. As Hamilton applies this concept to Christology, we many now speak of the chief example of God's indwelling mankind as having occurred in the incarnation. Here God indwelt Jesus. We can also perceive that the primary example of mankind's indwelling God is to be found in the resurrection. Here


22

Jesus is said to "live on" in God.[69] by "live on" it is meant that it is Jesus experiences, ideas and actions that were raised into God. We are therefore to understand that his resurrection is the most outstanding instance of God's desire and purpose to raise into Himself everything else that compliments his own character as well.[70]

It is obvious here that the resurrection is not interpreted literally. For Hamilton, the disciples had a God-given awareness (not self-generated, it is emphasized) that Jesus was somehow still both alive and present with them. This was the beginning of the Easter experience. But they id not have an actual encounter with the risen Lord as portrayed in the New Testament gospels.[71]

Hamilton realizes, however, that there are some serious criticisms regarding his views. One is that the uniqueness of Jesus' resurrection has not been properly maintained. Rather, this occurrence is only a model for other such actions of God.[72]

Another criticism (which is admitted by Hamilton to be a stronger one) in that, according to this interpretation, the "risen" Jesus is not really alive although the disciples believed that he was because of the aforementioned God-given awareness of this fact.

  


23

In other words, the New Testament writers witness to a risen Jesus who was really alive and the author agrees with this convection as well. Otherwise there would be no origin for the Easter faith. Yet, this thesis does not allow for the type of resurrection that would give rise to such a belief. Hamilton admits that his criticism is a valid one to a certain extent.[73]

The last scholar to be dealt with briefly at this time is Swiss philosopher Francis Schaeffer. Formerly an agnostic, Schaeffer became convinced through personal research that belief in God was rational.[74] Afterwards he became concerned to a large extent that rationality must be kept in religious belief and that knowledge must precede faith (but certainly not to the exclusion of faith).[75] Exploring this concept of rationality in Christian belief, Schaeffer came to espouse the view that God's revelation occurred in history and is thus open to verification.[76] An event which is reported to have happened can be examined and found to be either a valid claim or to be some ort of falsehood. This is the nature of historical revelation. For Schaeffer, the death and resurrection


24

of Jesus are both verifiable in this way. They are referred to a actual historical facts which literally occurred in our space-time world.[77]

We have in this chapter investigated both the importance of the resurrection of Jesus and the current theological approach to it as a religious occurrence. In addition, we have examined the views of several scholars from various other fields (especially history and philosophy) who have also shown varying degrees of interest in this event.

We have found that the resurrection is the central event in the Christian faith and thus of central importance in theology. Therefore the questions raised here concerning its character are both valid and consequential ones.

We have also seen that there appears to be a surprising interest in the resurrection by scholars in other fields besides religion. This especially appears to be the case in history and philosophy. The purpose for our investigation of several views in these two specific fields is threefold. First, it enables us to understand that this question is not one that is isolated to the field of

  


25

religion and theology alone. Second, it serves to familiarize us with some views of the resurrection that are surprisingly close to those proposed by some theologians which will be referred to constantly. Third, this previous discussion prepares the way for our later investigation of three scholars (one theologian, one historian and one philosopher) who deal with these questions concerning the resurrection in much more depth, thus relating all three fields together in a "search for the truth" on this issue.

 


26

Chapter II. The Possibility of Miracles Today

The question of whether or not miracles have occurred in the past (or whether they are possible today) is one that has far-reaching consequences much beyond the field of theology. We will turn now to an examination of some major possibilities.

A. Miracle and Myth

1. A Definition of Miracle

In search for a possible definition for "miracle", one encounter many approaches ad conclusions. However, there are several similarities and points concerning what most appear to be in agreement. We must realize, though, that the definition we arrive at actually has nothing to do with the problem of whether the events that are defined thusly really do occur. For example, many scholars who do not believe that miracles happen at all still define them as occurrences which are not caused by nature and which must be performed by God. They simply believe that no such events ever take place. Therefore we see that the definition does not mean that a certain type of phenomenon has happened.

Bultmann is just such a scholar who believes that our modern world is enough to make us reject all miracles. The ancient view of the world is obsolete and we no longer rely on its cosmology or mythological language.[1] Even so, it is recognized that at least

 


27

the New Testament defines miracles as events with occur due to the Supernatural intervention of God rather than by the power of nature. For Bultmann, the purpose of miracles is to express spiritual truths that many otherwise be unexplainable.[2]

Historian and philosopher David Hume, who also rejects the miraculous, relates that:

A miracle may be accurately defined a transgression of a law of nature by a particular volition of the Deity, or by the interposition of some invisible agent. (The italics are Hume's.)[3]

Once again we find that while Hume clearly rejects the miraculous (as we shall perceive in more detail later), he defines these occurrences as the intervention of God or of another invisible agent. Philosopher Richard Swinburne accepts essentially the same definition, realizing that in so doing he is close to Hume's view.[4]

English scholar C.S. Lewis defines miracles as follows:

I use the word Miracle to mean an interference with Nature by supernatural power. Unless there exists, in addition to Nature, something else which we may call the supernatural; there can be no miracles. (The italics are Lewis'.)[5]

Like the definition, here Lewis also conceives of miracles as having a direct affect on nature. But the miracles are seen as

 


28

being brought less forcefully into the world. Lewis perceives of nature as an entity which can receive such extraordinary occurrences into its own pattern of events when they are caused by Supernatural power. Thus they do interfere with the laws of nature, but do not break them.[6] These miracles are not taken for granted by the author, however, but are investigated to ascertain if they actually id occur.[7]

The last definition of miracles which we will state is that of theologian John McNaugher, who agrees with Lewis in asserting that these occurrences are out of the normal sequence of events in nature. They cannot be explained by natural processes, but are due to the agency of God. They are obvious to the senses and designed for the purpose of authenticating a message.[8]

In these five definitions of miracles there are obviously several similarities (as well as some differences). For instance, all five scholars are agreed (to varying extents) that real miracles require Supernatural intervention and are not to be explained naturally.[9] All five also believe that these occurrences have a direct relation to the laws of nature, requiring some sort of interference. Some think that miracles have a purpose. But all

 


29

are not agreed, for instance, as to whether these miracles actually occur or not. In other words, it is possible in this case to describe what an occurrence would entail if it were to happen, while not actually believing that there are such events. Nevertheless there is a surprising amount of similarity in these definitions scholars who disagree on this last point.

In this paper, the writer will refer to a miracle as an even which interferes with the laws of nature, but does not violate them. They cannot be explained by any natural causes (including man's power) and this must be accomplished by some type of Supernatural activity. They are effected for a purpose and may be perceived by man's senses. The question now is to ascertain if there really are such events.

2. A Definition of Myth

A discussion of miracles should ideally also include an inquiry into the meaning of myth. We will attempt to explore a couple of earlier meanings of the words and some modern definitions of it. We would thus endeavor to discover what myth is and what function it plays in society.

Originally,[10] myths were generally defined by scholars as fictitious narratives containing very little or no factual content.

 


30

They were mainly concerned with stories of gods, goddesses and question about the cosmos.[11] Because of such content, myths were judged to be simply fiction. The definition was one which implied the essential contradiction between myth and history.[12]

Later, the word also came to mean a fictitious story revolving around a historical personage, circumstance or event, but one which was not really factual.[13] Perhaps an example of this type of popular myth would be the narrative of how George Washington chopped down a cherry tree and chose the subsequent punishment rather than tell a lie concerning his actions.

There is much disagreement as to a suitable definition of myth today.[14] This is made even more difficult by the variations in the definition utilized by scholars from different disciplines.[15] One popular practice is to define myth as being the opposite of

 


31

history, thereby signifying that it is almost completely untrue in a factual sense.[16]

As used by most contemporary theologians and religions scholars, myth is not usually taken to be so unrealistic. The emphasis is clearly placed most often on the function of the myth and on what such a concept is supposed to accomplish in society. Thus, theologians are more interested in studying the message which the myth is meant to convey.

For nineteenth century theologian David Strauss, myth is the clothing for the expression of religious truths. For this reason, one must endeavor to ascertain the societal function and meaning given to a myth, trying to understand the religious message being communicated by means of this imagery. The importance of Strauss' view of myth is that before his time this concept was either not completely recognized or not applied consistently.[17]

Rudolf Bultmann believes that New Testament myth is essentially unhistorical, but that its primary purpose is to express existential truths about man.[18] Thus, this scholar also agrees that his question of the myth's purpose is the key one.[19] Bultmann freely

 


32

admits that the actual imagery of the myth is not the most important part of mythology. Rather, the recovery of its message about human existence is the most essential thing.[20] The stress here is also on understanding what the myth was intended to accomplish.

Few scholars have done more research on the idea of myth than has Mircea Eliade. For Eliade, myths are accounts of deeds which are always acts of creation, in that they speak of some reality coming into existence. Myths are very complex cultural factors whose main function is to serve as models for the rites and other important activities of humans. Thus myths present religious explanations for what is believed to have occurred. For this reason, a myth is perceived to be an actual reality in that is always depicts something that has happened, such as the beginning of the world or the fact of death.[21]

Eliade stresses the symbolic character of such myths. They are capable of revealing something which is deeper than known reality. Such symbols point to various facets of human existence. Perhaps the most important aspect of mythical symbolism is that truths can be expressed by this mode which can be expressed coherently in no other way. It is therefore very important to study the message of the myth. Scholars who do not discover this function of myth fail in their endeavor to understand this concept.[22]

 


33

For S.H. Hooke, myth is still viewed as being essentially nonhistorical, but it nevertheless a result of a particular circumstance and therefore it does have a purpose. Thus the proper approach is not to try to determine how much actual truth is contains, but rather to determine what the real function of the myth is--what it is supposed to accomplish. As with Eliade, Hooke stresses that the function of a myth is to use imagery to express truths that otherwise could not be explained.[23]

These definitions of myth have pointed to at least a few general conclusions with which many theologians seem to be in agreement, at least to a certain extent. Myths can be identified as the use of various types of imagery one's beliefs, customs or folklore. Myths are essentially nonhistorical but they may reflect actual occurrences and teach religious or moral truths. Myths do have a societal function.[24] They are often devices by which one can express what otherwise would be inexpressible, whether it concerns cosmology, man's existence, the Divine or one's religious and moral beliefs. In other words, myths serve the function of allowing various societies to speak of treasured beliefs, mysteries and customs in a way that ordinary language

 


34

might not quite be able to duplicate. This could be either because of a lack of proper words or a lack of the necessary knowledge needed to explain these things. For instance, mythical imagery could easily have been employed to explain certain cosmic events such as eclipses. In the way societies could pass on verbal or written accounts of the experiences. That this was an important function of myth is witnessed by the discoveries throughout various parts of the world pointing to this usage.[25]

These general conclusions will be the basis for the definition of myth that will be used in this paper. Briefly, myth will mainly be utilized to refer to the essentially nonhistorical use of imagery by societies in order to express certain beliefs, customs or events. They allow people to speak of realities that might be much harder to express apart from the use of this imagery.

The distinction between miracle and myth is an important one. It will be the purpose of the reminder of this paper to investigate the resurrection of Jesus in light of these definitions. Was this occurrence a myth voicing the beliefs of early Christendom, or was it a literal event requiring Supernatural action? Our investigation will thus view the evidence of each possibility in order to ascertain where is points in regard to this question. We agree with Wand in the assertion that it is very important to distinguish myth from history. The purpose of the myth must be determined and real history must not be confused with the myth.[26] Therefore, each has its own

 


35

purpose and it will be our task not to let the two become indiscriminately mixed.

B. Twentieth Century Science and Miracles

1. Introduction

It is common practice today to conceive of science and the miraculous as being totally opposed. Bultmann, for instance, rejects early Christian cosmology on the ground that it is opposed to modern science. All of our contemporary knowledge is based on science and this includes an application of its laws to the study of the New Testament.[27] Thus Bultmann speak of the relationship between science and miracles:

It is impossible to use electric light and the wireless and to avail ourselves of modern medical and surgical discoveries, and at the same time to believe in the New Testament world of spirits and miracles.[28]

Thus this scholar believes that we live in too modern an age to believe in miracles. The world is closed to such occurrences.[29] The Supernatural simply does not occur and is therefore quickly dismissed, often arbitrarily.[30] Others also agree with Bultmann's approach.[31]


36

This line of reasoning is not very recent, however. For a couple of hundred years prior to the twentieth century many have also held that science ruled miracles out. The universe was usually seen as being a closed system, meaning among other things, that it could not be interfered with by the Supernatural. James Jauncey defines it this way:

The standpoint of science was that nature was a 'closed universe'. This meant that everything within the universe was governed by an unvarying sequence of cause and effect. The universe was closed to any occurrence which deviate from this pattern….Whenever you had a certain combination of factors operating, the result was always the same and could not be different. Miracles, on the other hand, could not be fitted into this framework of cause and effect.[32]

This view of miracles is actually found very early in critical thought. We need not wait the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries to find this opinion expressed against the possibility of miracles. For instance, seventeenth century philosopher Benedict Spinoza (1632-1677) also opposed miraculous events which were said to break the laws of nature.[33]

Since the beginning of the twentieth century, however science has begun to change these former conceptions about the workings of nature. In men's past history there have been many scientific revolutions.[34] In the opinion of most, we are living today in the


37

midst of just such a revolution. Jauncey states in his Introduction entitle "The Scientific Revolution":

The evidences are pilling up that we are in the midst of the greatest [illegible word] in human living since the Renaissance. This is due to the tremendous explosion in scientific knowledge which has been occurring within the last few years. Even for those of us who have been close to the frontiers of science all of our lives, it is hard to believe what is happening.[35]

What are the results of these changes and how do they affect the possibility of miracles? Jauncey relates that one result of this scientific revolution is that today the idea of a closed universe is rejected. Scientific research has replaced this other view with a new understanding of nature.[36] Clark also notes that the idea of causality was dropped by science about one hundred years ago and the belief in a mechanistic universe has also come under attack.[37] The resulting new view of nature is sometimes referred to by such titles as the "Einsteinian-relativistic interpretation of "natural law" and perceived as being essentially opposed to "the world of Newtonian absolutes".[38] Thomas S. Kuhn also believed that the theories of Einstein are incompatible with the older ones formulated by Newton. In fact, we can only accept this Einsteinian system after recognizing that the theories of Newton were incorrect.[39]

A recent work by eminent German Physicist Werner Schaaffs has succeeded both in describing these comparatively recent trends


38

in physics and in dealing with the resultant influence on the possibility of miracles. Schaaffs informs us that the rejection of a closed universe by modern science took place about the turn of the century. In fact the year 1900 is seen as being the turning point for modern physics.[40] Therefore we can no longer scientifically hold to the belief in a closed universe as was the case in the nineteenth century.[41]

Schaaffs refers to the replacing of the closed universe view with the present view of physics as "double negation". This is because older opinions which were once used to negate all miracles are, in turn, negated themselves.[42] The old law of causation has been replaced by statistical description and this the law of probability.[43] To this we will turn directly. But we must fist remark that new theories in physics usually build upon older ideas and this appear at least somewhat to be a process of development (rather than a care of total displacement). The old views are thus expanded and corrected by the modern ones.[44] We will now take a closer look at some important developments in physics that have led to these conclusions.


39

2. Some Principles of Physics

We have been speaking of the modern view of physics and its negation of the eighteenth and nineteenth century belief in a closed universe where no outside intervention was believed to be possible. It should be mentioned in all fairness that not all scholars in these two centuries accepted this view of cause and effect in a mechanistic world[45] although it was very popular.[46] Therefore, before the twentieth century the world was, for the most part, conceived to be one of mechanical cause and effect. Any events which did not fit into this pattern, such as miracles, were often rejected immediately. It was the "reign of 'unalterable law'" in which it was imagined that one could be sure of events and in which miracles were simply not possibilities.[47]

With the emergence of the twentieth century experimentation in physics it was found that, contrary to the then accepted scientific belief, there was much uncertainty in out universe. It could not be predicted with complete accuracy how a particular event would occur. There were found to be invariable. It was beginning to be apparent that the universe could not be expected


40

to behave any one certain way all of the time.[48]

Even though we have been discussing the field of physics, it should be pointed out that this information definitely has had an effect on other fields of knowledge as well. This was obvious because, if these facts were true, then other studies also had to adjust to them. Later, for example, the effect of these discoveries on the discipline of history will be shown. Schaaffs notes, for instance, that few actually understand that the significance of these findings extend far beyond the field of physics.[49]

Some may object that these principles affect only questions which deal with the microcosm and therefore have no bearing on the topic miracles. Schaaffs deals with this very problem, concluding that one can work from any of three directions[50] to demonstrate that occurrences in the microcosm have a great bearing on events in the macrocosm. These reasons show that chain reactions can be caused by deviations individual atoms which eventually have macroscopic results. Thus, minute and unpredictable changes in

 


41

atomic processes cause major events in also become somewhat indeterminate and unpredictable. In fact, the uncertain pairing of microscopic transactions can either cause a macroscopic event to occur or keep it from occurring. Thus the macroscopic event itself becomes unpredictable and is it not within the reach of science to control it.[51]

It is true that microscopic event are more unpredictable than macroscopic ones, but both are often found to unexplainable.[52] For these reasons, both microscopic and macroscopic events "can be interpreted only as a law of probability."[53] This means that a "statement in science is seldom now considered true in itself, but only within a certain limit of probability…."[54] In other words, we can no longer consider a scientific statement as being absolute, but only probable to one extent or another. Statistical probabilities must be given to events according to the degree to which they can be expected to occur and not viewed as being positively certain as might be the case in a closed universe.

One use of statistics that is perhaps not at first obvious is that they "have enabled us to appreciate the extreme cases…"[55]


42

because "the rarer an event, the harder it is to determine a precise time for its occurrence. One can only assign a probability to it."[56] Therefore more common events receive a higher probability and rarer ones a lower probability. Unique events are given still lower chances of occurring. But this is intriguing in the case of these very rare events because "even the greatest probability cannot rule out the possibility that the event will occur tomorrow.[57] There is an infinite number of possibilities for such events to occur daily and thus they cannot be thought to be impossible.

Can giving a probability to rare events, as described above, have any relevance to the possibility or miracles occurring? Schaaffs answers in the affirmative:

Though a miracle is a rare, or perhaps even unique, event or experience, quite out of the ordinary, it can with comparative ease, as our example shows, be placed in a statistical framework. It has no intrinsic peculiarity requiring that is be placed outside that framework. Thus, a miracle though a rarity to be sure, is a phenomenon of natural law, for statistics are the essence of natural law.[58]

Therefore we see that for this German physicist miracles are possible. We will also note here that Montgomery, for one, agrees with this above analysis insists that the only way that an account of a miracle can be verified is by an "unprejudiced confrontation" with the sources which claim that such an event actually occurred. We need not try to ascertain a priori what is able to occur today (as was done in a closed universe), since almost anything is possible according to its statistical probability. In

 


43

other words, the "question is no longer what can happen, but what has happened" because "the universe since Einstein has opened up to the possibility of any event" (the italics are Montgomery's).[59] Therefore, we can only determine what has happened by investigating the sources in order to ascertain which events probably are and which events probably are not a part of history.

3. Miracles

Few understand how far-reaching these results in physics are and "how far beyond physics their significance extends."[] The knowledge this gained surpasses the bounds of physics and affects other fields such as theology.[] We have found that the belief in a mechanistic, closed universe is no longer valid and thus cannot be used to rule out miracles a priori, as in the past. We can only find out if an event has occurred or not by investigating the sources thoroughly. This could lead to either a positive or to a negative conclusion.

A key point we want to stress in this chapter is that these former world views can no longer be used, as contemporary theology often does,[62] against the occurrence of miracles. We are certainly not saying at this point that miracles do occur. But they can only

 


44

be disbelieved today on the merits of each. Montgomery drives this last point home in the following words, using the resurrection of Jesus as an example of a miracle:

To oppose the resurrection on the ground that miracles do not occur is, as we have noted earlier, both philosophically and scientifically irresponsible: philosophically, because on one below the status of a god could know the universe so well as to eliminate miracles a priori; and scientifically, because in the age of Einsteinian physics (so different from the world of Newtonian absolutes in which Hume formulated his classic anti-miraculous argument) the universe has opened up to all possibilities…"[63]

This is surely not to affirm that Einstein said that miracles would happen but only that there is always the possibility that they could, given our present concept of physics.

Concerning the conception of nature with which we have been working, we must mention that the results described above do not invalidate the idea of essential lawful order in nature. All are agreed that such a general order dies exist, even though it must only be described statistically.[64] In addition, as McNaugher explains, where there is no regularity in nature we cannot speak of any departure from it.[65] In other words, if nature were disorderly, it would be impossible to know if something had occurred that could be described irregular.

Thus, along with all recent studies, also affirm the belier in the regularity of nature. A true miracle, then (if there is such as occurrence), must interfere with this regularity, according


45

to our definition. Therefore, if miracles are to happen, nature cannot be the cause of them, but can only be open to their occurrence.[66]

Thus we hold that modern scholarship can no longer deny miracles simply by referring to a closed universe and to our civilization as being "too advanced". They can only be denied on the grounds of historical and philosophical (logical) research.

It may appear that there is too much reliance here on a current scientific world view that may change again in the future to yet another understanding of nature. To this there are at least two valid responses.

First and most important, it must be pointed out that an investigation into the possibility of miracles does not require the contemporary relativistic view of nature in order to arrive at valid conclusions. It is true that this modern view of science does help considerably both negating the old closed universe hypothesis and in allowing for the possibility that miracles of occur. However, it must be asserted that the procedure we will deal with later, namely, investigating an event first before any judgment is given concerning the probability of its occurring, does not depend on science. We cannot overstate this enough. If we were rest upon an existing view of nature we would always be in danger of having our system upset because of new ideas when this need not be the case. Regardless of the contemporary state of physics, we hold that an account of a miracle (as defined above)

 


46

should be investigated inductively to ascertain if it has occurred apart from any other world view of what can or cannot happen. Such is a much more logical and scholarly approach than beginning with presuppositions as to what is possible. These conclusions could this be maintained even if physics was not in the state in which we find it.[67] Thus the conclusions to be reached to not depend solely upon our modern understanding of science, but are rather based upon this aforementioned investigation of the reported facts.[68]

Second, Schaaffs answers this very question by asserting that physics is unlike other disciplines in that it does not regress backwards. "Accurate knowledge and the results of earlier research are never simply discarded; rather, they serve as building blocks for further advances.[69] He adds later that "the knowledge discovered in the present century will remain valid within the framework in which it was obtained.[70] Present concepts in physics

 


47

may even be broadened, but they do not disappear. This is because knowledge in this discipline is not discarded in order to return to older ideas.[71] As mentioned, the truths discovered in physics remain valid. Therefore even if we did rest our conclusions on the current scientific world view (although we do not, as stated above), they would still appear safe.

Before proceeding to the next chapter, it must be mentioned in all fairness that most men of science do not hold that this current view of physics give any preference to miracles.[72] Therefore we will conclude this chapter with the assertion of philosopher Gordon Clark, who is cautious in his evaluation of the relationship between miracles and modern physics. He feels that while some theological conservatives have gone too far in their application of scientific principles to the Supernatural, others have gone too far in the opposite to anything which is really miraculous. Clark believes that we can at least minimally conclude that the once-popular theories of a closed and mechanistic universe can no longer be used to invalidate miracles. In addition, neither these older theories or contemporary scientific ones can be used as objections against the Supernatural. While we cannot agree with those who believe that science gives preference to miracles, neither can we agree with those who believe that it forbids them.[73]


48

In other words, Clark's conclusion is stated in negative terms. Rather than holding that the universe allows for the miraculous, Clark simply states that we can no longer appropriate a scientific world view that rules out the miraculous. Thus he speaks not about what is possible in nature, as do many of the scholars we have dealt with above, but about what we cannot say about it. We cannot hold that science gives preferential treatment to miracles, but neither can the scientific world view be used to show that they cannot occur.[] This then is the conclusion we will work with, one which directly favors neother opinion. Therefore we are also left with the conclusion which we reached earlier--the decisions concerning the probability of certain miracles (such as the resurrection of Jesus) must be determined by a thorough investigation of the reported facts in order to ascertain of they actually happened.

  


49

Chapter III. History and Miracles

As stated above, this study is not based upon the findings of modern physics, but rather upon the idea that any accounts which claim that a miracle has occurred must be historically investigated in order for its veracity to be determined. Therefore we will look first at the concept of history that will be used in this work and then view the method of this investigation.

A. A Concept of History

The term "history" is used in various ways by different scholars. There is no uniform definition which is agreed to by all scholars, as numerous approaches and interpretations are commonly utilized.[1] Therefore it is not our purpose here to give a complete or exhaustive treatment of the contemporary definitions of history. However, it seems that there is at least some general agreement concerning the content of history.

Most historians are agreed that history includes at least two major factors--the actual events in particular and also the recording of these events. Thus this discipline is mainly concerned with what has happened and how these occurrences have been annotated. It is this conception which will form the core understanding of history as it will be used in this work. Other elements are surely involved, as will now be noted. But inclusion of these two


50

major ideas are essential and are thus the foundation of this concept as it will be used here.[2]

Now we surely do not mean to affirm that the presence of these two elements is all that is involved in a definition of history. Rather, these are the ones which seem to reoccur most often. However, a few other factors that are part of this discussion should also be mentioned quickly.

First, there is always a subjective factor involved in the writing of history. For instance, the historian must select the material which he will (and will not) cover. The historical event is obviously objective. It is the recording of the event that introduces subjective factors. For W.H. Walsh, the subjectivity of the writer is present, but it is not a real serious roadblock to the obtaining of objective history. This subjectivity can be allowed for its efforts can be overcome.[3] Wand agrees with Walsh in asserting that the best approach to take towards history is one of caution,[4] as we should try and recognize this subjective bias


51

and then make the proper allowance for it.[5]

We well also endeavor to allow for this subjective factor in our investigation of the resurrection. This occurrence has been reported as an objective historical event and we must ascertain of it is the best explanation for the known facts.

Second, we find that history cannot reach the point where it is totally positive of its findings in all instances. As with physics, so there is also a certain amount of dependence on probability in history as well.[6]

For instance, Ernest Nagel, who accepts a deterministic view of history, admits that he does so in spite of the convictions of contemporary physicists who almost unanimously hold the opposite viewpoint.[7] The conclusions of these scientists have had an affect on historians, for the accepted scientific view against a deterministic universe has also helped to turn historians against a deterministic view of history.[8]

Nagel lists five main reasons why historical determinism is generally rejected by so many historians today. First is the argument from the absence of any developmental laws or patterns in history. Second is the argument based on the inability to explain and predict event in human history. The third argument concerns the appearance of the novel in historical occurrences.


52

Fourth is the argument from the chance events which are also a part of history. The fifth argument concerns the conflicting results when one attempts to make the concept of a deterministic world compatible with the freedom and moral duty of human beings.[9]

It is because of these and other similar finding that so many historians have rejected the deterministic view of history. Nagel further states (to reiterate the point), that the findings of modern physics, which also oppose determinism, have been a key factor that has exercised a direct influence on a similar rejection of this concept by most historians.[10] Montgomery concurs in this belief that contemporary science has made it impossible for historians to accept a closed system of natural causes.[11]

The appearance of these chance and novel events mentioned above, together with the aforementioned inability to explain or predict many other occurrences, has helped to further the use of probabilities in historical studies (as well as in scientific investigation).[12] Historians both recognize and utilize this concept of probability. For instance, Montgomery observes that historical studies can never the one hundred percentile level in certainty.[13] Ronald VanderMolen agrees completely with Montgomery's


53

assessment and thus accepts the belief that historical scholarship is not completely positive of its findings. In fact, historians must not fail to allow for this amount of uncertainty.[14] For this reason Montgomery opts for a critical investigation of the sources in question, with the decision about the occurrence of any specific event being based upon the probability of the evidence. In fact, probability is referred to as the only sufficient guide for a historian.[15] Wand also notes that we cannot be as sure of historical investigation as was thought possible in the past.[16] However, we must make our judgments as to which facts are most probable according to the historical evidence.[17]

These elements, then, are to be included in a contemporary treatment of history. While it has not been our purpose to deal with this subject exhaustively, we have come to some conclusions on the concept of history as it will be used in this work. We will refer to history as both the occurrence of past events and the recording of them. Realizing that there is always a certain amount of the subjective in this recording, allowance must be made for it as much as is possible in order of objective data to be obtained. Realizing also that in speaking of history we are dealing with probabilities, it will be our desire to ascertain as nearly as is possible which facts best fit the evidence. With these probabilities


54

and uncertainties there is always room for the possibility of any even, however high the probability may be against it.[18] Events can therefore not be ruled out (either scientifically or historically) before they are researched. The only answer is a thorough investigation of the evidence.

B. Investigating the Historical Events

1. Historical Research and Investigation

It is the opinion of most historians today that the veracity of past events can be discovered (within a certain probability) by a careful investigation of the facts.[19] Walsh notes that since these events have occurred in the past, they are only accessible by a study of the historical evidence. Although the historian himself will not be able to participate in the event that has already occurred (unless he was originally there), he is able to inspect the relevant data such as written documents and various other records, structures or archeological finds. Upon such confirmation as this the historian must obtain his evidence. This is what Walsh feels is the working principle of historical research.[20]


55

Of course, what the existing data and written sources reveal is not usually automatically accepted as being true. It is therefore the job of the historian to critically investigate the available claims in order to ascertain as closely as possible what has happened. This includes the procedure of determining if the sources best support the claims that are made in them. The proper results can be obtained even though there exists this need to determine which facts best fit the evidence. Then it is the duty of the historian to formulate the facts based upon this groundwork.[21] One is therefore to decide upon the evidence at hand--that which is shown to be the most probably conclusion.

Even claims of miracles must be investigated in this way, since they cannot be ruled out a priori, as noted above. On this subject Montgomery asserts:

But can the modern man accept a 'miracle' such s the resurrection?... For us, unlike people of the Newtonian epoch, the universe is no longer a tight, safe, predictable playing-field in which we know all the rules. Since Einstein no modern man has had the right to rule out the 'natural law' …The problem of 'miracle', then, must be solved in the realm of historical investigation…[22]

As Montgomery concludes, since we cannot decide in advance what can happen, we must determine, by historical research, what really has happened already.[23]

We must quickly point out here that miracles are not to believed simply because they are Supernatural. In fact, we would


56

desire to be the more careful before accepting a miracle-claim as a historical event, But, on the other hand, we must also guard against the presupposition that miracles cannot occur at all. There is no real basis, either scientific or historical, for this presupposition.[24] Although many are skeptical about the reality of miracles, it may be that a supernatural explanation fits the facts bet and is the most probable solution.[25]

On the last point of skepticism Wand has made a very pertinent point. His words were specifically directed at the historical skepticism of theologian Van Harvey, but Want points out that the same can also be applied to others of this persuasion as well. Harvey argued that we cannot accept the New Testament accounts of the empty tomb even though there is much historical evidence in favor of them and no convincing evidence contrary to them. To this Wand responds:

We may well ask Harvey how a critical historian can do anything else than decide on the evidence before him--unless indeed he already holds some secret which will invalidate in advance any evidence that can be brought in favour of the phenomenon in question? The plain fact is that in this kind of argument the skeptic is not functioning as a historian at all. He starts with the assumption that there could be no corporeal resurrection since that would be against nature….That is to say, he rejects the evidence because he does not life a conclusion that it may be used to support.[26]

It appears that Wand's point is well taken here. What also can the historian do except investigate the available evidence and make


57

a decision based on it? Since this is the way that other historical facts must be decided (as we have seen above) it seems that we do not have the right to demand different criteria simply because, as Wand notes, we do not like or agree with the conclusions. We must therefore approach this subject with an open mind, endeavoring to ascertain which explanation is the most probable.[27]

Now some may judge that Wand's conclusions are those of the theological "fundamentalist" who endeavors to prove every word of Scripture as being true . TO this is should be remarked that not only does this Oxford scholar object to such beliefs,[28] he holds to the quite "contemporary" theological opinion that while some of the New Testament is historical and trustworthy, some is also simply propaganda which was written without any claims to being objectively historical. Thus he cannot accept the view that the Bible itself is the guarantee and proof that all of Christianity was completely historical.[29] Because of this, Wand believes that we should inquire into whatever mythical elements could possibly be present in the texts. But, at the same time, we cannot allow the portions that evidence indicates are historical to be labeled as myth.[30]

Wand's conclusion in these matters is that we must approach these ancient documents cautiously. Bias and subjective factors


58

must be allowed for and dealt with accordingly. But, in spite of all this, we may find that the Supernatural explanation is more historically probable than the natural one. In this case we must be prepared to accept the miraculous conclusion.[31]

2. The Resurrection and Historical Investigation

According to Wand, the resurrection is the central claim of New Testament Christianity and as such it cannot simply be ignored.[32] Neither should we be content to leave the question simply by affirming that the original disciples believed that Jesus had risen. Since it is the center of the Christian faith it should be carefully investigated. We must inquire into this belief in order to ascertain whether or not it is valid.[33]

Other Historians also agree to the need for such research. Ancient historian Paul Maier also believes that the historical evidence for the resurrection must be investigated. Then we can better judge whether it can be referred to as an actual part of history.[34] Another ancient historian, Edwin Yamauchi, agrees that we must investigate this occurrence in order to conclude if it is best explained as myth or as history.[35] We have discussed


59

Montgomery's preference to historically investigate this even as well.[36]

Therefore, after dealing with the problem for faith and reason in the next chapter, we will turn to this investigation.[37] The New Testament authors certainly claimed that Jesus rose from the dead, meaning literally that he appeared to many of the early Christians after having actually died. No one doubts that his is what the accounts report. It remains for us to endeavor to determine the facticity of these claims.

We have in this chapter explained the concept of history that is it be used in the work. We have also determined that history, like science, cannot rule out the possibility or miracles a priori; that is, without investigating the available evidence and deciding upon it, To this end we have briefly described the approaches taken by several historians as to historical research and investigation. Procedures such as these will be used in our own investigation of the resurrection of Jesus.


60

Chapter IV. Reason and Faith

It has been said that Christian history and thought is a history of the opposition between faith and reason. This is a reference to the continual conflict between these two aspects of the Christian life-the spiritual and the rational.[1] There has always seemed to be a variety of views on the subject, often intermingled and overlapping. Historian of philosophy Etienne Gilson has dealt with several of these opinions in this work Reason and Revelation in the Middle Ages.[2] For instance, early church theologian Tertullian believed not only that faith was primary, but that all reference to human philosophy or other teachings should be excluded.[3] Passing to the twelfth century, we find Saint Bernard voicing a similar opinion in favor of faith alone.[4]

A second view was that of Augustine, who held that one's reason and understanding do play a part, but a secondary one since faith is to precede them. Therefore we must exercise faith first before we can understand.[5] Another exponent of this view was Anselm.[6]

Gilson finds that a third important view was voiced by the twelfth century Arabian philosopher Averroes. Although his was not


61

a Christian system of thought, it did influence Christianity. For Averroes, reason was primary and faith was subordinated to it.[7]

The fourth view was that of Thomas Aquinas, who endeavored to find harmony between faith and reason. He believed that some truths could be known only by revelation while others could be attained by reason.[8]

This is just a sample of some of the possibilities when one views the history of opinions of the relationship between faith and reason. Some favor the use of either faith or reason exclusively. Some give a place to both, while subordinating one to the other. Either reason is seen as being subordinate to faith or vice versa. Others try to find a balance between the two methods. In this work a system will be set forth which is both a workable one and one that is justified by the facts.

A. Reason and Faith: Definitions

In order to lay a groundwork for our discussion on this topic, this stud will begin with a look at the dictionary definitions of these two terms.[9] The American Dictionary of the


62

English Language defines reason as follows:

The basis or motive for an action, decision, or conviction….A declaration made to explain of justify an action, decision, or conviction….The capacity for rational thought, inference or discrimination….To…think logically….To talk or argue logically or persuasively….To persuade or dissuade (someone) with reasons.[10]

According to this definition, reason includes at least two concepts. First, reason is the capacity to infer, discriminate or even to think rationally. Second, reason is the explanation or outworking of this capacity. This second concept includes (among other things) several components parts. Reason is defined as being the basis or motive for one's decisions or convictions, or a statement explaining or justifying these decisions or convictions. Reason is also the ability to think logically or to argue persuasively, including persuading (or dissuading) someone one way or another.[11]

If this definition was shown to be a valid one, other conclusions could be drawn from these two concepts of reason as well. For instance, reason would be at the very basis of all of our knowledge, for one cannot even have the capacity to think apart from reason (by definition). Without reason the explanation or outworking of this capacity would also fail to be accounted for because rational thought is defined as being at the basis of all actions, decisions or convictions. In fact, we cannot even formulate these convictions or make these decisions (intellectual or otherwise) except by utilizing reason. Therefore reason is the beginning of knowledge


63

since it becomes obvious that we could not even think in the sense which we are accustomed to, except by reason. Considering the definition, we would have to think without formulating any convictions, making any decisions or coming to any conclusions in order to do so apart from a rational process. Finally, any attempt to counteract these conclusions or argue otherwise is also reason, again by definition.

However, as we have stated above, dictionary definitions cannot in themselves solves philosophical problems such as this one. Therefore, after faith is defined, the views of those argue in favor of these definitions will later be investigated.

The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language defines faith as:

A confident belief in the truth, value, or trustworthiness of a person, idea, or thing….A system of religious beliefs.[12]

Faith, then, is trust or belief in a person, thing, idea, value or truth. Belief itself is defined as mental action centered in a conviction that is thought to be valid.[13] We have already determined in our previous definition that the basis for such actions and convictions is reason.[14] In addition, belief generally involves thinking of some sort, even if it is only the elemental thought that


64

what is told to believe is "good".[15] Both of these procedures of thinking about one's faith, along with the convictions and decisions that often accompany them, are grounded in reason, by definition. Even the capacity to understand these beliefs is part of the cognitive process and has its basis in reason.[16]

There are two general reasons why faith is usually exercised. Some believe by intuitive conviction, while others require reasonable persuasion and rational argument (indeed, some claim an interest in both). But the capacity for both is acquired by reason, as defined above. This is because the ability even to hold convictions and the ability to reason concerning them is rational.[17]

Our study has thus far shown that faith must rely upon reason as its basis. However, this discussion has not so far been one of finding which of the two is the most important and it should not be construed as such. Therefore we will look briefly at this question now.

Even though reason composes the groundwork, we still hold that faith is the most important element of religious belief for two main reasons. First, it is not possible to logically and reasonably


65

prove everything in the Christian faith. Thus faith extends beyond the reaches of this reason, which is more limited. Since we can only speak of varying degrees of probability, as stated above, any religious system which places such research at the apex of achievement will find that it is very limited in what is presented for belief. The realm of faith and hope would be narrowed quite considerably.

Second, although reason can yield true data from a logical investigation of the facts, faith is capable of transcending the rational when one puts trust in these facts. Therefore, one exercises faith based on the reasonable probabilities. Without such belief one could not speak of the Christian faith. God cannot be known by reasonable processes (beyond the knowledge that He exists), but rather a faith is needed which appropriates and trusts the evidence, with definite ethical implications for one's life. Without this primary importance of faith and these accompanying ethical implications, Christianity would not be a faith system. This is almost the unanimous witness of Christianity through the centuries, and it has a sound basis. While reason and knowledge are very important, especially as a basis for belief, faith is more so.[18] Reason is thus not the ultimate. This position is also accepted in this work. Faith should remain in this pre-eminent position, being careful to note that this is a reasonable faith based on


66

the facts and not a leap in the dark. More will be said in favor of this opinion below.

So we now reach our conclusion pertinent to the results of these definition and the roles they play in the issue between faith and reason. We have so far concluded that while reason is temporally primary, faith is the most important. Neither should be excluded and both should be used in its proper place. These definitions, however, will not be regarded as the final word in this discussion, nor will it be assumed that they can totally solve the issues. Therefore it is advantageous to turn now to those who also hold to some of the results arrived at here.

B. Reason and Faith: Scholarly Views

A study of definitions has revealed that reason must be the basis of all thinking processes, including the mental activity of faith. While reason is this temporally first, when speaking in the context of Christian theology, faith is the most important.

Several contemporary scholar of the have come to similar conclusions based upon personal studies of the evidence. Secular theologian Paul Van Buren believes that faith always requires a thinking process. This is because faith always requires a thinking process. This is because faith usually includes both logical contemplation of historical sources, and these, in turn, involve reasoning. Any type of Christian faith that neglects these processes is quite inadequate.[19]


67

Theologian John R. Stott also believes that faith is not irrational. It is neither credulity or optimism.[20] Rather, it is a trust based upon reason--rational belief. As such faith does not contradict or oppose reason, but rather it is essentially complimented by it.[21]

For philosopher Francis Schaeffer, rationality, knowledge and faith are all related. Rationality is very important, but not to the exclusion of the other elements. A balance must be kept between each. Nevertheless, we cannot expect faith to be exercised prior to a rational investigation of the evidence, or before a proper knowledge and understanding of the truth has first been achieved. These conditions precede faith.[22]

Theologian Wolfhart Pannenberg stresses the need for grounding faith on an objective, rational basis. In two essays entitled "Insight and Faith" and "Faith and Reason" he sets forth his rationale for this belief. Faith cannot stand alone and be its own criteria and proof for belief. This is because the subjective qualities of one's own faith alone provide no solid reasons as to why it is also good for another individual. The original question as to whether the grounds of this faith are solid is never answered. There is no logical reason to accept it. Therefore a knowledge


68

based upon reason must precede faith.[25]

As pointed out earlier, Montgomery holds that there must be an objective, historical basis for faith. Faith that is not based on some such reasonable evidence can give no logical reason as to why it should be accepted over other alternatives. Faith cannot verify itself and neither can an "experience" demonstrate its own validity in and of itself. Therefore we have no reason to accept any faith as being valid if there are no grounds upon which to base this claim.[24]

We have briefly investigated the views of five scholars on the question of the relationship between reason and faith. We will turn now to the rationale behind these views, as to why reason held to precede faith. The general conviction seems to be, first, that faith, must be based upon knowledge and that, second, reason begins the entire process and provides the basis for this knowledge. We will examine these premises more closely.

First, faith must be based upon a knowledge of certain facts which are at least believed to be true. In order for one to have a

 


69

faith-conviction there must ideally be this basis for belief. At the very least (in the absence of any intellectual or rational investigation), religious faith is trust in the existence of God or a reliance upon certain believed truths.[25] Therefore, religious faith must be grounded on some sort of knowledge, even if it is only the belief that God does (or does not, in the case of atheism) exist.[26] When we perceive that the Christian faith is this based upon knowledge, we can then view this knowledge as preceding the faith.[27] Even some of the end results of faith, such as various


70

kinds of action or ethical involvement, are due at least partially to the attainment of this prior understanding.[28]

Second, reason begins the process and provides the basis for this knowledge. We have seen that faith-conviction relies on knowledge and that this must involve some thinking, if only at the rudimentary level. Indeed, Van Buren states that real faith is only possible when one thinks[29] and Stott asserts that one cannot have faith at all apart from such cogitation.[30] But thinking is a rational process which requires the use of reason.[31] Therefore, reason both begins this process and provides the framework for it.[32]

In addition, faith must have an objective basis. Without such a foundation, one would never know if the grounds for one's belief were solid or not. Apart from a foundation of reasonable knowledge, faith is not capable of substantiating itself. Its subjective qualities provide no rational basis or criteria according to which its trustworthiness may be ascertained. For instance, one cannot appeal to one's personal spiritual experiences for the needed authority factor. Montgomery notes that an appeal to such private experiences is an unconvincing testimony, since it is sometimes hard to tell if the heart-felt experiences of another amount to


71

anything more than heartburn![33] At first this appears to be simply a humorous illustration, but upon closer examination it is found to contain much truth. How can we hope to differentiate between real experiences or beliefs and false ones of there is no factual criteria which gives us at least some idea as to what may be most trustworthy? A faith which is grounded upon rational facts and which rests upon an objective basis is in a much better position to ascertain its trustworthiness than is a faith which is admittedly irrational and subjective in its approach. It is true that one may prefer the latter, but this does not answer the question of how one might verify this faith even for oneself, let alone for others.

It is also true that the rational approach does not always lead to a valid faith. But is appears that it would be much better off in view of this question of verification than would a faith which does not (or cannot) utilize any rational method at all. Indeed, an intelligent investor does not often risk funds on an enterprise which gives no valid reasons to make such an investment seem worthwhile. Even hunches and premonitions are usually based on some sort of knowledge or reason, even if it is "secret information". In a similar way, faith should also be based upon a rational groundwork.

Apart from a objective faith which is based upon a logical examination of the facts, there is no way to ascertain of such


72

 beliefs are valid or not. No amount of wishful thinking can make the facts any more truthful. No matter how intense one's faith is, one cannot make this faith any more valid. Faith must therefore have an objective basis or else one would not be able to ascertain if it is simply spurious.

Pannenberg also believes that we must reject a subjective Christian faith which is based on one's personal experiences. He does so for at least two reasons. First, such private experiences cannot be obligatory for others because they lack factual, objective evidence and therefore are usually only capable, at the most of convincing oneself.[34] Second, this subjectivism disregards the fact that the very center of Christianity is based on Divine initiative. Men everywhere are able to investigate the foundations of this religion in order to ascertain as closely as possible if events such as the resurrection have actually occurred. The opportunity to investigate the claims of Christianity is open to anyone who wants to study them and is not relegated to the perusal of a select few.[35] Therefore, the Christian faith is most properly


73

objective, open to a rational confrontation with the facts and not subjective or irrational.[36]

The same conclusion that was reached with regard to trying to substantiate Christianity by one's personal, subjective experience also applies to those who endeavor to point to the proclaimed message as the basis for the faith. This approach also fails in that the obvious question concerns whether there is a real reason to accept it or not. If the reason is unconvincing, it would seem that we would lack a sound basis for accepting it. Further, the message apart from any rational coercion cannot show why it should be accepted over another alternative, or even over a contrary view. In other words, the message is not self-authenticating but must also provide objective reasons to back up its claim to truth.[37]

By "objective reason" we are referring to the need for faith to investigate the historical (or other) evidence and make its decision upon which facts best fit the case. For Schaeffer, faith is based upon just such an examination of the events which Christianity claims have already occurred in history, such as the resurrection. One cannot be asked to exercise faith in the Christian message until the evidence has been investigated.[38] Montgomery agrees that faith begins in an investigation of the objective, historical events and


74

rests in the probability of the findings.[39] But we must remember that faith is based on the events and not vice versa.[40] In other words, faith is not formulated apart from the facts, hoping that there is some evidence to support this venture. Rather, one believers because the facts appear reasonable. Pannenberg also stresses this last point, asserting that an individual does not bring an already existing faith to the events, but exercise this faith only after an open-mind look at the events.[41]

As for the question of importance, we found earlier that reason was temporally primary while faith was more important in a theological context. We found this to be true for two main reasons. First, the whole of Christian teachings and belief cannot be explained completely in terms of reason. Second, when we speak in a theological context belief takes on a central importance, as it transcends reason. Faith must personally appropriate the facts, which involves ethical implications for one's life. This is chiefly because we are dealing with the existence and teach of God. (the Greek Theos, root word of theology), a doctrine which cannot be dealt with adequately in the realm of reason alone. The importance of faith is primary here, as witnessed by centuries of Christian thought.


75

Does contemporary thought offer similar reasons for giving faith the place of primary importance while placing reason first temporally? We must answer here in the affirmative. It is especially noteworthy that the same scholars who we have been dealing with in our previous discussions, those who hold that reason in the place of prime importance in the end. Even the same two reasons used above (or very similar ones) are employed. First, Pannenberg notes that the doctrines of Christianity can never be explained completely in terms of reason. There will always be a remainder.[42] Second, Pannenberg further relates that no one can come to know God strictly by his own reason. A good example here is the Christian teachings concerning salvation. Even though reason provides the original basis, knowledge is still not capable of securing salvation because it depends finally upon the appropriation of faith and reliance in God and personal surrender to Him[43] Thus faith is based upon rational probabilities, but the final expression of it transcends the rational.

Montgomery also comes to similar conclusions. Faith is based upon the probabilities which emerge from an investigation of the objective facts and the final step of salvation is a appropriation of this fact by means of faith. As such, faith and commitment to 


76

God through Jesus Christ is the final step of salvation, as it accomplishes something which reason could never do.[44]

Wand adds an interesting point here. While faith is dependent upon reason and builds upon its more conclusive basis, fait is still more important in that it is more intimate and personal than knowledge. Thus it makes use of the framework of reason and then goes beyond the rational.[45]

It may become apparent at this point that reason and faith, when properly understood, actually compliment each other. Both have their own roles to play and each are very important.[46] These roles, as we have shown above, consist of faith operating on the basis of reason.[47] However, the two are not in competition with each other, but rather cooperate together. In this way they are found to be quite compatible.[48] The result is that head and heart should ideally work with, and not against each other.[49]

The conclusion which we have reached in this chapter is that faith can only be built upon reason, meaning that reason is temporally first in this process. This has been found to be the case both


77

from an investigation of definitions and from a logical examination of the evidence. From the first study we found that we cannot even think in the way we are accustomed to, let alone exercise faith, apart from a rational process. For instance, real faith involves convictions and mental action. These can only be held by some variety of thinking and they also require reason, however naïve. One can exercise valid faith, however, even if one is not able to personally investigate the facts, as mentioned above. From the latter study we have not only verified this, but we have concluded in addition that a subjective, irrational faith can provide no logical grounds as to why it should be accepted. If there is no rationale for this faith, there can be no objective criteria on which its claim to truth can be based. Therefore one cannot ascertain if the message based on such a faith should be accepted. If there is no rationale for this truth can be based. Therefore one cannot ascertain if the message based on such a faith should be accepted or not. Without any criteria of objective data on which to judge its contents, there is no logical way to distinguish one faith-message from a rival one. In fact, one is hard pressed for any evidence on which one's religious experience may be distinguished from any other human emotion, unless it is grounded in logical reason and investigation. Even an intense faith apart from such an objective basis cannot make faith any more valid. Therefore, we hold that for faith to be intelligible it must be based on rational knowledge.

We must be careful to point out once again that a rational approach to faith may not solve every last problem, but it does provide the best grounds on which to base faith, as shown above. Without this approach there would be no real way that one could verify these conclusions with any confidence. We this encounter historical probabilities once again, as it appears that arguing


78

from objective, historical data and logical evidence seems to provide the best way of arriving at the most probable result. So while the rational approach is not infallible, it does provide the best means of gaining testable and verifiable foundation for faith. If we abandon the rational, we must also abandon our hopes of gaining such objective and verifiable results.[50]

An irrational or strictly subjective faith is not capable of providing such answers. It cannot verify itself or demonstrate its own validity. Neither can it answer the question of whether its grounds for faith are solid or not. Because of this lack of evidence it cannot show why it should be accepted over other possibilities. Such a faith cannot provide a logical reason as to why it should be accepted, since there are no testable grounds on which to base this claim. Neither can such belief make faith any more truthful. There is no logical reason to accept this faith.

Although reason is temporally first, faith was found to be the most important as an end result. This is because, first, all of Christian belief cannot be accounted for rationally. Second, in the context of theology, faith can do what reason cannot quite accomplish in dealing with the existence and teachings of God. Although based upon reason, faith transcends the rational in providing a means by which one can trust in the reasonable findings of one's aforementioned investigation, applying the results to one's life.


79

Lastly, we discussed the need to bring reason and faith together. We must present them henceforth as being entirely compatible and not in competition with each other, recognizing that each has a role to play. Reason forms the basis and is temporally first while faith is more essential and important.

In the historical and logical investigation which will now follow, we will endeavor to combine the essentials of our last three chapters. The scientific world view can no longer be used to rule out the miraculous. Rather we must speak in terms of probabilities and investigate each miracle-claim. Here history also plays a part. Utilizing the concept of historical investigation outlined above, we will examine the possibilities of belief and nonbelief in the resurrection of Jesus. Again we must decide upon historical probability and accept as factual that explanation which best fits the facts. The philosophical discussion just concluded will also be utilized here. We must maintain throughout this relationship between reason and faith.[51]

It is advantageous to turn now to our historical and logical investigation of three key possibilities (and several related ones) concerning belief and nonbelief in the resurrection of Jesus. The


80

findings in the fields of physics, history and philosophy will be combined in a effort to ascertain which possibility best fits the facts.


81

 

PART 2

POSSOBLE SOLUTIONS TO THE QUESTION

OF THE RESURRECTION OF JESUS

 


82

Chapter V. Possibility Number One: That the Resurrection Did Not Occur

A. David Hume: An Introduction

The first possibility to be dealt with here is that the resurrection did not literally occur. We will begin by investigating the views of one very important scholar who held this opinion, turning later to several other related views[1] The scholar we will use as a representative example is historian and philosopher David Hume (1711-1776).

This choice of Hume as the primary scholar to be dealt with here is one based on several closely-related reasons. It is quite doubtful that an author could be chosen who has had more influence on this question of miracle. Hume's essay "Of Miracles" has been so influential that one can hardly even deal with this question at all without discussing his work.[2] The importance of this short writing has been reflected by its enormous affect upon contemporary theology and philosophy.[3] Even conservative theologian Wilbur M. Smith admits that this essay contains the strongest argument ever

 


83

presented against the belief in miracles.[4] Therefore Hume is an excellent example of one who rejects belief in any miracle such as the resurrection. The popularity and high repute of his essay among other scholars who hold similar views further reflects the trustworthiness of this choice.[5]

In order to more correctly understand Hume's contribution to the question of miracles, it is important to look briefly at some of the intellectual trends of the time in which he lived according to Heick, English deism is a movement which may arbitrarily be said to have covered the century and a half from Herbert of Cherbury in 1624 to Hume in 1776. Deistic trends were intrinsically in agreement with similar proclivities in French and German thought.[6]

During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in England we find the popularity of various types of deism that sometimes allowed for varying amounts of Divine revelation. However, these brands of deism were generally not of the variety which is often referred to today as "the clockmaker's theory, whereby God was said to have made the world and later abandoned it to its own existence without any guidance whatsoever. This is a later definition of the word,


84

formulated when it became necessary to differentiate between atheism, theism and pantheism. In eighteenth century England, therefore, the word was not often used as a conscious attempt to differentiate between deism and theism, as it is today. Rather, the word was used to describe scholars who were opposed to atheism.[7]

In defending religion, the deists of this period depended upon reason to justify faith. In fact, reason was usually perceived to be the most important part of one's belief. Traditional Christian dogmas were attacked as not conforming to the application of this reason. Some of the emerging views were quite radical for these times. For instance, the results included doubts of traditional revelation and authority, and an opposition to Supernatural miracles and wonder. There was a growing conviction that the search for a natural religions was valid and that a "common ground" should be found among other religions, since all were believed to be ways to God.[8] Attempts at formulating such a natural approach to faith based upon the different religions were developed in works such as Herbert of Cherbury's "Common Notions Concerning Religion".[9]

One major development of a large portion of English deism was


85

the emerging emphasis on empiricism, culminating in Hume. Experience was believed to be the criterion for obtaining knowledge. Even a very brief survey of some of these trends reveals this emphasis. An early empiricist, Francis Bacon, based his experiments and other observations upon the experience arrived at by the sense. This experience was gained by an application of the inductive method of ascertaining truth. Thomas Hobbs also sought to base all knowledge upon the criteria of sense experience. For John Locke, men acquire ideas by experience. In fact, even Divine revelation is perceived by reason and experience.[10]

Hume also followed the emphasis on experience. He believed that this experience was the foundation for all knowledge.[11] Although this method in not infallible, postulates were to be judge according to the probability of the experience. As we shall see below, this forms the center of his polemic against miracles.[12]

Hume's work is by no means limited to this field of philosophy. He is well known in this area, but in the middle of his scholarly career he turned away from such studies to other interests like history and ethics.[] In fact, his best known work is very probably his multi-volumed masterpiece entitled The History of England.[14]


86

It was poorly received by the public in the initial stages, but soon became a well-recognized and very popular work. It was considered a classic for many years.[15]

Earlier several reasons were observed for choosing David Hume as a representative example of one who holds that the resurrection, as a miracle, could not occur. Also just completed was a brief look at the background of the period in which he lived. It is desirable now to turn our attention to his extremely influential essay "Of Miracles".

B. David Hume's Argument and a Critique

In his essay "Of Miracles", David Hume argues from what he is convinced is mankind's experience against all real miraculous events. At the outset, miracles are defined as events which violate nature's laws. Hume postulates further that such events, if proven to have occurred, must be caused by some Supernatural power of other such agency.[16]

In order to determine if such events have actually happened, one must test the available data empirically. This consists of viewing the experiential evidence for the miracle-claim on the one


87

hand an the experience of the reliability of the laws of nature on the other. Then one can ascertain which is more strongly attested. This test is therefore one based, once again, on the testimony of experience. The experience of miracles in pitted against the experience supporting the uniformity of nature. Here Hume concludes that it is more probable that the experience favoring the laws of nature is more reliable and the miracle is therefore rejected. Since each case of miracle comes against similar experiential data, these occurrences are rejected as a whole.[17] An important note here, however is that Hume realized that his argument had not disproved the existence of God.[18]

Thus we perceive that for this scholar, the experience of miracles is to be rejected in favor of the experience of the laws of nature. In addition to the reasoning given above, Hume also makes use of four supportive points. First, there are no historical accounts of miracles when are attested by enough reputable men so as to make the event probable. Second, people are inclined to want to speak of extraordinary experiences, even to the point of fabricating the miraculous in order to spread religious truths. Third, miraculous are cited as having occurred mainly in areas of ignorance or even barbarism. Fourth, the miraculous events in one religion destroy the probability that those of another faith are also true and via versa. Therefore, accounts of such Supernatural events in different religions nullify each other. Thus, all are

 


88

eliminated by the others.[19]

Now at the outset we must agree that this appears to be quite a reliable system in which to test relevant data. Hume seems to have found a valuable method and one can easily see how it has appealed to scholars. But in order to ascertain if these first impressions are correct ones, let us proceed to the text itself. It is the conviction of this writer that there are at least four major problems with Hume's approach to miracles--four chief criticisms which endanger the very heart of his polemic.

The first major criticism of Hume's essay is that he incorrectly defines both the essence of a miracle and the nature of the evidence for and against it. He states:

A miracle is a violation of the laws of nature; and as a firm and unalterable experience has established these laws, the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, is as entire as any argument from experience can possibly by imagined.[20]

As in the actual definition of miracles stated by Hume above, we again above, we again observe that these events are perceived to contradict and violate nature's laws. They are said to do so because the totality of experience relates that these laws cannot be interfered with or broken. This experience is "firm and unalterable". Later Hume describes it as "uniform experience".[21]


89

Immediately we can perceive a logical error in reasoning here. Hume fails to begin the investigation with an impartial look at the facts. Rather, his very definition rules miracles out because of an arbitrary and unproven assumption and it is therefore not a valid one. His definition is based upon the idea that the totality of experience rests against the miracle, when such is far from proven. There definitely are miracle-claims that are experientially based, but these are brushed aside by the assumed superiority of other varieties of experience. But Hume cannot know if the claims made by supernaturalists are able to invalidate the claims made against miracles apart from an investigation of the facts.

An example of this could readily be provided. Hume is definitely thinking at least somewhat in terms of the miracles of Jesus.[22] But rather than speaking specifically concerning the chief miracle-claim of the Christian faith, which is the resurrection of Jesus, he speaks only generally of the resurrection of any dead individual and then promptly inform his readers that such an occurrence has never happened when he has not presented any examination of the facts. He has no evidence that his has never occurred. He further concludes from this (without any new evidence) that in a similar way all experience opposes every miracle.[23] Therefore we have a good example of circular reasoning. Dead men are assumed never to rise, and because all experience is arbitrarily perceived to stand against such as an event, all experience also must oppose other miracles as well. The evidence for miracles is simple ruled out. But this can only logically be done after an investigation

 


90

of the evidence. Thus Hume assumes that which he must demonstrate.

Oxford scholar C.S. Lewis also recognizes this weakness and develops it into a trenchant criticism of Hume's position. Lewis relates:

Now of course we must agree with Hume that if there is absolutely 'uniform experience' against miracles, if in other words they have never happened, why then they never have. Unfortunately we know the experience against them to be uniform only if we know that all reports of them are false. And we can know all the reports to be false only if we know already that miracles have never occurred. In fact, we are arguing in a circle.[24]

Lewis has clearly perceived the problem here. Hume can only claim that all experience supports his view if he has first ascertained that all other experience is false. But since he has not investigated the other evidence, he can only state that it is false by assuming that miracles cannot occur. Thus he reasons circularly.

It goes without saying that one cannot disallow miracles simply by defining them so that they cannot happen. Circular definitions are clearly unsatisfactory.[25] But, as we have seen, Hume defines miracles to be impossible in light of the experience which testifies to the existence of laws in nature. This is done without any real investigation to determine if the experience on behalf of miracles can establish their validity. He must somehow know this latter experience to be false and he can only know that it if so by assuming that miracles cannot occur in the first place, as Lewis explains.


91

It may be that one aggress with Hume's conclusions that nature does rule out miracles. But the point here is that one cannot define this to be the case or arrange the "facts" in such an order that this assumption is supported. It is a matter of philosophical and historical debate.[26]

A further issue here is the place that should be given to experience for the laws of nature. We mentioned above in chapter two that we also agree with Hume in asserting that nature behaves by certain laws. We could not speak of miracles as being abnormalities apart from recognizing a normal pattern.[27] But Hume asserts that the existence of these laws is sufficient to disprove all experience of miracles.[28] At this point there are many scholars who would disagree.[29] Just because there are laws in nature, this does not mean that occasional abnormalities cannot occur. Such laws regulate the inner workings of nature and describe what will happen if the system is left to itself. But these laws do not dictate the possible results of Supernatural interferences from the outside. Now we have not as yet established if such Supernatural influence is possible. But the point here is that Hume is simply begging the question when he assumes that the experience for the laws of nature is superior to experience (if established) for the miraculous.[30]

 


92

This is so in that the very experience which he dismisses as nonexistent or as inferior, if established to be probable, would overrule the supposedly stronger experience for the laws of nature. This is because miracles involve the Supernatural intervention into nature, and if such intervention was shown to be probable via a miracle, it would show that the laws of nature could be temporarily suspended. Thus, valid experience for a miracle would actually be superior to experience for the laws of nature. Yet Hume fails to sufficiently investigate this experience for the miraculous. Therefore Hume cannot use the laws of nature as an absolute rule which cannot ever be broken.[31]

C.S. Lewis also accepts this last criticism of Hume as a valid one. He points out:

Probabilities of the kind that Hume is concerned with hold inside the framework of an assumed Uniformity of Nature. When the question of miracles is raised we are asking about the validity of perfection of the frame itself. No study or probabilities inside a given frame can ever tell us how probable it is that the frame itself can be violated.[32]

In other words, Lewis charges Hume only answering question which fall unto the framework of his assumed view of a completely uniform nature, when in reality we should be asking whether the frame itself can be violated. Thus Hume is concerned with things


93

which might of might not occur within a limited system when he should rather be concerned with the system outside of this restricted area. Is it possible that this little system of nature, as trustworthy as it might be in and of itself, could be interrupted from the outside (as with a miracle)? Burtt levels a similar criticism at Hume.[33]

It is now easier to understand why experience in favor of miracles, if found to be probable, is so important here. If such was found to be the case, it would demonstrate that the laws of nature could be temporarily suspended, thus making the empirical claims in favor of the miracle dominant over the empirical claims for nature's laws. But by refusing to investigate such miracle-claims, Hume thereby rejects evidence that could easily disrupt his assumptions and show a miracle to be probable.

Therefore we see that Hume is guilty both of formulating a circular definition and of begging the question with regard to the importance of experience concerning the laws of nature. But these two errors are in turn used improperly as the heart of his polemic. Hume further states about miracles:

There must, therefore, be a uniform experience against every miraculous event, otherwise the event would not merit that appellation. And as a uniform experience amounts to a proof, there is here a direct and full proof, from the nature of the fact, against the existence of any miracle… (Italics are Hume's).[34]


94

Here we see three more obvious errors of logic. First, Hume persists in formulating a circular definition of miracles, assuming that they cannot occur from the very outset. As we have said above, he can only know that there is uniform experience against all miracles if he has investigated all of the serious claims. Since he has not done so, he can only know that all experience opposes miracles by ruling that they cannot happen in the first place. This is clearly circular and has already been adequately shown to be an incorrect procedure. In addition, he still is working only within the framework of the laws of nature and thus does not take account of possible interferences from the outside. This, likewise, has been shown to be incorrect.

Second, we perceive an additional misuse of experience. Experience is now uniformly allied against all miraculous events. As we mentioned above, the reason all experience is assumed to agree with Hume's first prohibition against miracles is that these events have already events have already been determined not to take place, by definition. Therefore, all reliable experience will indeed coincide with this since the opposite is defined as an impossibility. But it is clearly not possible to assume an important statement like this. It is not logically correct to argue circularly in order to answer supernaturalists who cite experience for miracles simply be defining all experience so that it opposes or even eliminates miracles. But this is exactly what Hume does, as experience is explicitly defined so that if it does not provide evidence against such events, then the said occurrence "would not merit that appellation."[35] This is a new


95

prohibitive placed against miracles by experience. In other words, unless all experience stands against an event, it cannot be referred to as a miracle. In order for a miracle to be claimed as such, its existence must immediately be opposed by all experience. This is done without proof or investigation of the miracles. Is this a proper approach? This a second circular definition and subsequent begging of the question is introduced and the problem is further compounded. First, experience of nature and second, the uniformity of experience are both placed against miracles in such a way (without any evidence) that these events are said to be impossible. The burden of the second (uniformity of experience) rests on the solidity of the first (experience of nature), which solidity has all but been proven. The moment an event becomes designated as a miracle, it is snuffed out of existence arbitrarily.

Third, and in spite of all this lack of proper evidence, Hume insists on stating that this constitutes a proof--"a direct and full proof" against any brand of miraculous event.[36] The argument to a second of the same and on to the concluding "proof".

But this "proof" turns out to be nothing more than an assumed conclusion. It is a good example of an ipse dixit or an unsupported assertion.[37] But if one premise of a syllogism breaks down, the


96

whole is invalidated.[38] One can demonstrate anything if definitions are allowed to be all-inclusive and contain the conclusion which is to be proven as a given. Therefore we perceive that Hume's "proof" fails. It indeed relies on the previously given definition of a miracle. It is a solid example of circular reasoning.[39]

It is easier now to see why many scholars have objected to various aspects Hume's approach top miracles. He assumes here that which he wishes to prove, but which he has not investigated.[40] In spite of claiming to deal with the miracles of the Christian faith,[41] he refuses to deal with any specific New Testament miracles, but simply rules them out as being impossible.[42] In fact, one scholar notes that Hume felt so strongly about the impossibility of miracles which are part of the basis of faith for religious systems that claims to the contrary did not even have to be examined specifically.[43] This sounds like anything but an honest attempt to arrive at the proper facts concerning opinions which disagree with one's own! It is indeed an intellectually secure person who can know that these events can never occur without any investigation whatsoever. But judging from the work in question, this appears to be the attitude of this scholar.


97

Again, C.S. Lewis points to yet another example of circular reasoning in this essay on miracles. For Hume the two questions "Do miracles occur" and "Is the course of nature absolutely uniform?" are one and the same, simply asked differently. But "by sleight of hand" Hume answers "Yes" to the second question and then uses if for answering "No" to the first question. The real issue which he endeavors to answer is never really dealt with at all. We still do not really know if miracles occur. Therefore Hume "gets the answer to one form of the question by assuming the answer to another form of the same question."[44] Again we find an example of circular reasoning.

We have found, first of all, that Hume commits a series of logical errors. In particular, these usually consist of arguing circularly (especially with regard to a definition of miracles) and by begging the question in using unproven and unsupported assumptions (especially in reference to the believed absolute authority of the laws of nature and the negligible value of any experience of miracles). These arguments alone are enough to invalidate Hume's entire thesis against miracles. We could also "prove" that miraculous events do occur by definition and by accepting all experience for miracles, while rejecting all experience for the laws of nature. Then we could conclude that all other experience must agree with this. To do so would of course prove nothing. But it could be made as


98

logically valid as Hume's argument. However, there are yet three other points of attack that we must make with regards to Hume's work on miracles.

The second major criticism of Hume's essay concerns his use of the four supportive points which appear to expand his beliefs against miracles.[45] It is our contention that he then ignores a series of miracles which he even admits fulfills these four "conditions", leaving the way open to the possibility that other miracles also fulfill them. The case in question concerns a series of reputed miracles performed among the Jansenists in seventeenth-century France. Hume's own investigation of these occurrences proves ever interesting indeed, in light of his four supportive points.

Pertaining to the first point, Hume admits that these miracles were "proved upon the spot, before judges of unquestioned integrity, attested by witnesses of credit and distinction…" and lists several very reputable persons who were reported either to have witnessed them personally or who investigated the cases later. These include such persons as a well-known and respected lieutenant of police, a number of physicians, a duke, a well-respected cardinal, 120 witnesses who were quite influential in Paris an even a list


99

of several famous scholars (including Pascal and Racine).[46] Surely these can be counted as a satisfactory number of reputable witnesses.

As for the second point, Hume also admits that these reported miracles were investigated by the Jesuits and other groups who were enemies of these teachings. This group included the previously mentioned lieutenant of police, whose job it was to expose or suppress the reported miracles. His attempt was unsuccessful. The Molinist party also tried to discredit these occurrences and ended up attributing the miracles to the devil, thus admitting that they occurred. In another instance, the acting queen of France also wished to expose these miracles. She sent her personal physician to investigate them, only to have him return as a Jansenist convert. In fact, none of the antagonists who were sent to investigate this situation were apparently ale to uncover any falsehoods at all.[47] We are not making any judgments as to what may or may not have happened here.[48] But it is plain to see that these may enemies of these reports were not lying to make the miracles appear plausible. Nor were they trying to delight in the spreading of these reports, for it was their own desire to expose these facts. Indeed, they had a private interest in disproving them. Even Hume admits to


100

the fact that many of the witnesses were reliable.[49] Therefore we can assert that these witnesses have not upheld the second point.

Concerning the third supportive point, neither can we hold that these events occurred among ignorant and backward peoples. Not only did they occur in one of the more advanced countries of the world not long before Hume's own time, but Hume explicitly states that all of this happened "in a learned age". Once again he admits that the conditions stated in one of his points do not pertain to these miracles.[50]

Hume's fourth supportive point also fails as an adequate explanation here. Even if the miracles purported to have occurred in some religions were able to "cancel" those in other faiths (which is a dubious assertion), the logical procedure would be first to investigate instances of these reports. It there were some instances which appear to be better documented than others, as in the case cited here, it would not be logical to abrogate these because of the existence of "lesser" miracles which are also reported in other religions. It would be more reasonable to uphold the events which best fit the facts, as outlined above. Here it is curious to note that Hume adopts a similar procedure. He investigates what he feels are two such "lesser" miracles before discussing the Jansenist reports. The first two are clearly found to be falsehoods.[51]


101

Later he recognizes that the Jansenist reports fit the facts better. But he apparently does not endeavor to rule out the latter accounts by using the former two, and logically so.[52]

Hume's fourth point would only be plausible if one assumed that all accounts of miracles were true, thereby causing some to believe that there was a possible conflict of ideologies. But since all are clearly not factual, we are left most logically with the need to investigate each case on its own merits. Thus we cannot rule out an event which is well-attested simply because other accounts of miracles also exist, for we cannot know but that the latter ones are the falsehoods and the former one factual. This can only be determined by an investigation of the miracle-claims. Therefore the last point is also found not to be applicable here as a critique of these miracles.

 For these reasons we can perceive that Hume's four supportive points do not succeed as a valid critique of the miracles in the case of the Jansenist reports. Nor have they disproved the testimonies. In other words, these four "prerequisites" for miracles have all been fulfilled. In fact, Hume seems willing to admit his assertion. The following statement could be construed as his acknowledgment that the first three in particular meet the requirements. Speaking of the Jansenist claims he states:

But what is more extraordinary; many of the miracles were immediately proved upon the spot, before judges of unquestioned integrity, attested by witnesses of credit and distinction, in a learned age, and on the most eminent theatre that is now in the world.[53]


102

Here Hume informs us that there were reputable witnesses of these occurrences (point one), men of sufficient integrity and unquestioned character so as to militate against the charges both of lying (or forgery) and of the unscrupulous spreading of tales in order to "tickle the ears" of men (point two). In addition, these reports were proclaimed to have happened in an intellectual age in one of the most advanced countries of the world (point three). We have already shown above that the fourth point also cannot be used here because we cannot rule out a well-attested even a priori simply because of the testimony of other similar events which often do not fit any of the facts at all. We can only judge on the evidence at hand. Neither does Hume specifically assert that the fourth point applies here.

We have now established that Hume felt that the Jansenist miracles were well-attested cases. The human testimony in favor of these occurrences is impressive, especially in view of the fact that it concerns claims of Supernatural events.[54] Therefore it would be very valuable to se how Hume responded to the question of whether these were valid claims to the miraculous or not. To this suggestion Hume responded concerning these events:

Where shall we find such a number of circumstances, agreeing to the corroboration of one fact? And what have we to oppose such a cloud of witnesses, but the absolute impossibility or miraculous nature of the events, which they relate? And this surely, in the eyes of all reasonable people, will alone be regarded as a sufficient refutation.[55]


103

It appears that Hume's dismissal if the miraculous is here a very arbitrary one. Even when all of the information adds up in support of a fact, it cannot be maintained to be true if it is Supernatural in origin. Even if it is one of the most corroborated facts in terms of human testimony and experience, Hume says we must reject it simply because miracles are impossible. A more blatant case of circular reasoning may be difficult to produce. When evidence is found for a miracle, it is held not to apply simply because such events do not occur when this may be the very evidence capable of demonstrating that they do occur. One would just naturally assume that Hume was really interested in exploring the possibility of miracles in an essay of this scope. Rather, we find that his belief in that miracles do not occur and that no examination of experience for them can establish that they even probably do.[56] Thus we hold that Hume first assumes that miracles could never occur and then disregards the evidence on behalf of them.[57]

Even if one could show that Hume did have an adequate reason to distrust these reported Jansenist miracles, the former charge


104

that he arbitrarily dismisses possible evidence in favor of miracles for faulty reasons can still be maintained for two reasons. First, he makes a similar statement earlier in the essay which is not related to the Jansenist issue. After his circular definition of miracles which is dealt with above, he remarks that:

…no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony be of such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous, than the facts, which it endeavors to establish…always reject the greater miracle.[58]

Again we perceive that Hume is convinced that no amount of testimony can establish a miracle. Even when his criteria (the presence of sufficient experience of the event) has been satisfied he hold that miracles are impossible. Therefore, as explained in the first major objection to Hume's essay given above, Hume is also guilty of employing unsupported assumptions. Miracles are rejected just because they are Supernatural even when they are found to have adequate experience supporting their reality.

Second, even if Hume continued to rely on other conclusions (such as the miracles in other religions) to oppose the miraculous in the instance of the Jansenist reports, he discredits the fact that the available evidence might be sufficient to establish this experience as miraculous even if no other miracles had over occurred. In other words, the evidence that is dismissed might be enough to demonstrate the reality of these events as the supreme example of the Supernatural whether other such claims were valid or not. If an event has occurred it is made no less realistic because there


105

are other claims to similar occurrences in existence.

Therefore we find that his second major criticism of Hume's essay is also valid. His four supportive points are highly objectionable in the first place, mainly because a large portion of our currently accepted history would be subject to much doubt if these were viewed as the norm by which facts are to be judged as being correct. For instance, how much of our accepted world history is made up if events which were not attested by a goodly number of unquestionably intelligent and educated men who in themselves are sufficient to guard against all kinds or error and delusion? One might indeed question large amounts of history because of a lack of conformity to this rule. Or how much history is prejudiced by the fact that the person reporting stood to gain much by the acceptance of these events, such as Julius Caesar's reports of his victories over the barbarians? And surely many other events took place among ignorant of backward nations? Since Hume includes the Greek and Roman civilizations as falling into this category (because miracles were reported by them),[59] are we to doubt the history of these entire periods, to say nothing of ancient Babylon, for instance? One begins to note the many problems involved in such an application of these four criteria to history. Yet this history is accepted as being quite reputable and trustworthy. As Richard Whately once so aptly noted, the same method which Hume employed to dismiss the miracles from the life of Jesus would also remove the unique elements from the life of Napoleon. Such reconstructing of history is correctly


106

seen as being self-condemning and very problematical.[60]

But as we have also found, Hume fails to do justice to miraculous even when they have attainted a high level of credibility because of the weight of the experiential testimony in their favor. Such evidence would most likely be sufficient to corroborate other historical events. Therefore is appears that we would be impelled to grant probability to certain miracles if they best account for the available evidence. And if Hume errs in his evaluation in cases such as the above, it is reasonable to hold events if they are found to be the best explanations for what occurred.[61]

The third major criticism of Hume's essay revolves around the fact that his entire work depends upon an assumed uniformity in nature. Hume rejects miracles because of man's experiences of this of cause and effect by assuming that the course of nature will continue (and that it always has continued) exactly as it is now perceived. However, the fact is that we know only a small part of nature and cannot be sure that what we doo know will continue to be the same in the future (or that it has continued this way throughout the past).


107

What makes this argument all the more persuasive is that Hume himself recognized the fact that we cannot accept cause and effect as being valid.[62] This is especially evident in his little work An Abstract of a Treatise of Human Nature,[63] where Hume explains why we cannot reasonably accept this notion. It is customary to expect an effect to follow a cause, but there are no reasonable or logical grounds for it.[64]

Since cause and effect are no longer held to be valid,[65] there is really no logical reason for believing that the uniformity of the laws of nature can rule out the miraculous. Neither can we assert that the state of nature has ruled out miracles in the past, because the uniformity needed for such as assertion also cannot be demonstrated. In other words, Hume's contention that the experience of mankind does not know of any valid cases of miracles because of the uniformity of nature is not only invalid, but it contradicts his own statements to the contrary.

This is actually a very powerful argument against Hume's entire essay, which relies on man's supposed experience of the uniformity


108

of the laws of nature.[66] This experience, based upon the reliableness of nature's laws, is the very center of his polemic against miracles, as shown above.[67] It is central that it is held that no miracle could have occurred, simply because of this uniformity. Hume holds that even if one could find a probability or proof for a miracle, it would then run up against the "proof" of this uniform conception of nature, meaning that it could never occur anyway.[68]

But now we find that this method can no longer be used as a basis for this rejection of miracles. There is not only a lack of proof that nature must act in this way, but we have even found that we cannot speak if this type of causality in nature because it is no longer a valid concept (see especially chapter two above). This means that the entire basis of Hume's system as it now stands must be abandoned. If such a probability for a miracle were found to exist, as postulated above, there is therefore no "proof" from nature left to oppose it. This would also apply to instances of miracle-claims in past history, if they were shown to be probable, because these new concepts of nature would have applied then, as well. Once again we perceive that miracles cannot be opposed by a uniform, causal view of nature. Hume's objection to miracles is therefore quite defective.

C.S. Lewis agrees in this critique of Hume. He states in a


109

similar vein of thought:

The whole idea of Probability (as Hume understands it) depends on the principle of the Uniformity of Nature….We observe many regularities in Nature. But of course all the observations that men have made or will make while the race lasts cover only a minute fraction of the events that actually go on. Our observations would therefore be of no use unless we felt sure that Nature when we are not watching her behaves in the same way as when we are: in other words, unless we believed in the Uniformity of Nature. Experience therefore cannot prove uniformity, because uniformity has to be assumed before experience proves anything….The off thing is that no man know this better than Hume. His Essay On Miracles is quite inconsistent with the more radical, and honourable, skepticism of his man work (Italics are Lewis').[69]

Here Lewis also recognizes that Hume's entire argument depends on the uniformity of nature. But there is no way we can know, much less prove, this belief. We observe nature by our senses and incorporate it into our experience. But all of the experience of mankind is but a small part of the whole. In order to say that nature acts completely uniformly with no interruptions (as Hume asserts) would be to know all of nature. This is once again circular reasoning because, as Lewis points out, one must assume uniformity in all of nature in order to say that we experience the same when we do not know the whole of it. We must simply believe it is the same. In other words, one must already have assumed that nature is completely uniform and acting in a causal way when the evidence indicates otherwise. Lewis also notes that Hume accepted similar arguments against the causality of nature in his other works.

Our two former conclusions must therefore stand in light of this knowledge. First, Hume's basis for rejecting miracles is not valid.


110

One cannot reject a miraculous event if it best fits the evidence simply because of an assumed uniformity in nature, especially when such uniformity has been shown not to exist. Cause and effect would have to be in operation before Hume's arguments could even begin to be asserted. But even Hume himself rejects this view of nature. Thus nothing is left but to abandon the very basis of his reasoning. Second, this means that the question now concerns which facts best fit the evidence, turning us once again to an investigation of these facts. It a miracle in past history is found to offer the best explanation of the evidence, it can no longer be opposed because of the belief that these things simply do not happen or because nature opposes such an event.

Our fourth major criticism of Hume's essay arises from the second and third criticisms, A positive aspect of Hume's philosophy is that he relies heavily upon probabilities, which has been shown above to be the conviction of modern thought. In addition, Hume rejected many of the then-popular theories concerning cause and effect and the accompanying implications based upon a closed universe. In an age when it was popular to accept a mechanistic view of the universe, Hume insisted that it remain open.[70] In this sense, at least, his thoughts mat be viewed as a forerunner of some of the modern theories which also postulate an open universe.

HHowever, a problem arises when we try to reconcile Hume's belief in an open universe with his previous rejection of miracles.


111

Rather than allowing the evidence to speak for itself (since evidence for miracles cannot be ruled out a priori or by an improper view of nature), as might be expected when one holds the above positions with regard to nature, Hume

transgresses his own position to rule out miracles. He does not allow the miraculous even when the evidence is sufficient to point to a probability (criticism two) and then he dismisses the miraculous as a whole by accepting a view of nature which he himself has already dismissed (criticism three).

Therefore a fourth major criticism is arrived at here. While he accepts quite a modern view of the universe in many senses, he becomes a pre-modern is his treatment of miracles. In other words, he is not self-consistent in his philosophy. His treatment of miracles shows signs of a pre-modern critical consciousness, for he proposes to accept an open universe but rejects miracles because of a closed view of nature,[71] and he proposes to base his work on probabilities, but arbitrarily rules out a probable miracle. Thus he is internally inconsistent as well as reverting to this pre-modern consciousness.

We therefore hold that all four of these major criticisms of Hume are valid. He is first guilty of committing a serious of


112

logical blunders. He argues circularly[72] several times, usually with regard to his definition of miracles and often begs the question by using unsupported assumptions, such as the negligible value of any experience of miracles. He also fails here in refusing to investigate any of these events when this very investigation could reveal a valid miracle. Second, Hume fails to accept miraculous events even when they are found to be well-attested by human experience. He still rejects them for arbitrary reasons even after he admits the high credibility of this attestation. Third, Hume rejects miracles because of a view of nature that not only way false, but that he even rejected himself. Yet the belief in this uniformity of nature is the center of his polemic against miracles. Therefore the very apex of his polemic against miracles must be rejected. Fourth, while Hume is modern in many of his conceptions of nature opting for the use of probabilities and rejecting cause and effect and the subsequent uniform view of nature), he reverts to a pre-modern stage in his attempt to prove that no actual miracles have ever occurred. In arguing against miracles he gives little weight to miraculous probabilities and employs an incorrect view of nature which he even rejected. Thus he is both pre-modern and self-inconsistent here.

It is obvious that these criticisms invalidate Hume's treatment of miracles. These errors and improper conclusions in Hume's work were not as readily detected in the eighteenth century because the


113

Enlightenment intellect continued to prevail in scholarly circles. As will become even more apparent in chapter six, the desire was usually to reject miracles in the first place and Hume's essay provided the needed authority for such a venture.

It thus goes without saying that Hume's polemic against miracles, while appearing to be strong argument at the outset, fails when closely investigated. This system cannot therefore be used at all to invalidate or rule out miracle-claims. A more proper approach may have been to define miracles without any inherent statement as to the possibility of their occurring. Then it would have been possible to investigate the available experience in order to determine the extent of its agreement. We are thus confronted once again with the need to investigate the evidence to better ascertain what has occurred. Such a historical investigation of the documents making such miracle-claims is therefore needed, as concluded in chapter four above. In the specific case of the resurrection of Jesus, empirical claims have been made which report experiential evidence for the appearances of the risen Lord. These are the accounts which must be examined in order to ascertain if this event is the best explanation for the facts.


114

Chapter VI. Possibility Number One: Other Similar Views

It is hard to estimate exactly the influence that Hume's essay "Of Miracles" has had upon the intellectual world since its appearance in 1748. However, we may most assuredly determine that its affect upon theology has been extremely great. Many scholars have viewed it as the determining argument against the existence of any miraculous even. This is true both of the older nineteenth century liberal theologians and of the more contemporary twentieth century theologians. Some refer directly to Hume as the source for this rejection of miracles as being due to the belief that our experience of nature completely opposes any such violation of its laws. It is important to look briefly at both this direct and indirect evidence for Hume's influence.

We are informed by John Hermann Randall, Jr. that since the appearance of Hume's essay, religious liberals have rejected any belief in miracles. Nineteenth century liberalism[1] as a whole became convinced by this work that there could be no interference


115

 with nature from any miraculous events.[2] Montgomery agrees with this assertion that nineteenth century liberal theology followed Hume's rejection of miracles.[3]

An excellent example of this rejection is seen in the works of German theologian David Strauss, one of the most vigorous critics of the New Testament who ever lived. In his two-volumed work A New Life of Jesus (first translated into English in 1865, shortly after the German edition), Strauss specifically asserted that Hume's essay was so conclusive is disproving miracles that the question had now been settled.[4] Miracles simply could not be allowed to contradict nature.[5]

Strauss' stance on this question, one which follows Hume's critique, is a typical one taken by nineteenth century liberalism. Friedrich Schleiermacher was also of the opinion that a real miracle would involve the suspension of the laws of nature. Such miracles occur most often where there is little knowledge of these laws. We should abandon such miracles as being superfluous, for they are not able to bring us closer to a recognition of Christ. Besides, science and religion agree here that there are no absolute instances of such


116

an event. A more perfect view of God, one requiring man's absolute dependence, needs no such miracles to support its cause.[6] For this reason, Schleiermacher preferred to see all events as being miraculous, including the most common and natural ones. In fact, events such as those which were supposed to have broken the laws of nature by Supernatural intervention are really not miracles at all.[7]

Other instances such as these are common in liberal theology. Bruno Baur followed Strauss in strongly insisting that we can admit of no events which deny the laws of nature. Rather, nature's laws are upheld by religion and not insulted by occurrence such as miracles.[8] Ernst Renan postulated that Jesus was not aware that there were any laws pattern of nature, Jesus believed that miracles were very common occurrences and nothing about which one should be surprised.[9] Adolf Harnack also held that ancient peoples had no concept of the strictures of the laws of nature. But today we realize that no events can occur which interrupt nature. As a


117

result, miracles do not happen and we cannot believe in the accounts of them.[10]

This rejection of the miraculous, revealing a dependence upon Hume's thesis is not relegated only to nineteenth century theology, however.[11] As shown above, contemporary twentieth century critical theology has pursed a similar pattern of thought. It usually espouses either the belief that miracles cannot (and should not) be validated, or, often relying directly on Hume's arguments, that all miracles should simply be dismissed as impossible.[12] For instance, Paul Tillich holds that miracles cannot interfere with the laws of nature. Any theology attempting to make them do such is distorting the Biblical view of God.[13] Bultmann believes that our modern conception of nature has rendered miracles impossible. The natural laws are such that they make the world a reality that is closed to the miraculous. We are thus too advanced to believe in the New Testament accounts of such Supernatural workings.[14] John A.T. Robinson likewise believes that miracles such as Jesus' incarnation can only be described as myths because in our scientific


118

age we realize that natural processes cannot be interrupted by Supernatural intervention. The entire New Testament cosmology must be ruled out for these reasons.[15] We have briefly explored some major theories proposed by those who follow Hume in arguing against the occurrence of all miraculous events. Many scholars utilized these and similar views which opposed all miracles in deducing from them specific hypotheses against the belief in a literal resurrection of Jesus.

To be sure, the milieu of the eighteenth century, in which Hume formulated his anti-miraculous argument, was different from the milieu of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, in which these religious liberals applied Hume's views. In the nineteenth century there were the philosophical systems of Immanuel Kant, stressing morality and Friedrich Hegel, who emphasized a theology of reason and development.[16] In the later half of the nineteenth and on into the twentieth centuries, Darwinism extended its influence. Historical events such as the French Revolution and the two World Wars also added to this climate of change. The secularity of these differences, however, on the question of miracles these liberal theologians ever since the eighteenth century continued to follow Hume, believing that such events were impossible.


119

A. Heinrich Paulus

Very possible the most noteworthy scholar who endeavored to apply Immanuel Kant's thought to New Testament studies was Heinrich Paulus.[17] This German theologian also rejected miracles for reasons which were quite similar to those listed above. The Biblical witnesses are believed to have had a deficient knowledge of the laws of nature, especially in not knowing of nature's secondary causes. Therefore they wrongly believed that Supernatural events actually occurred. However, when we discover the true workings of nature, we a re said to find that the events which were once considered to be miraculous can no longer be considered as such. This is because these occurrences are found to proceed according to natural law. Thus Paulus proceeded to employ naturalistic explanations for the New Testament accounts of miracles.[18]

The resurrection of Jesus was also given such a natural explanation. For Paulus, Christ did not die on the cross. He was taken down before death overcame him and later resuscitated gradually in the grave. The spear wound in the side had not immediately killed him, but had merely served as a blood-letting device and encouraged his recovery. Later an earthquake was additionally helpful in rolling away the very large stone from the front of the grave, thus enabling Jesus' escape. He obtained the apparel of a gardener and then proceeded to arrange for a meeting with his


120

disciples. After several visits with them, he realized that he was dying. He then held one last meeting on the Mount of Olives. As he moved away from them, he was obscured from their sight by a cloud was not seen by them again Jesus died, but in a place unknown to the twelve, who referred to this event as an "ascension".[19]

According to this conjecture, usually referred to as the "swoon theory" of the resurrection, Paulus plainly conceived of this event as one operating by natural processes. There was no Supernatural intervention involved. Thus Jesus was not believed to have risen from the dead.

The swoon theory did not originate with Paulus, but was quite popular with several other scholars throughout the first half of the nineteenth century. It was an especially common interpretation of the resurrection found in the so-called fictitious accounts of the life of Jesus which appeared during this same period of time.[20] These works were imaginative portrayals of life of Jesus, often very similar to novels. The use of fiction was quite apparent, as the author weaved various plots and counter-plots into an attempt to portray Jesus' life in a certain light. The non-historical ingenuity of the writer was usually quite noticeable. As a result, these works were seen as having little credibility or esteem.[21]


121

Paulus' work differed in that it was not one of the above imaginative lives. His work was both more logical and more respectable exponent of this theory.[22]

Strangely enough, liberal theologians were some of the most ardent critics of the swoon theory. By far the most famous critique was given by David Strauss himself. He pointed out that in order for this theory to be true, Jesus would have come forth from the grave half dead, one who was quite visibly ill and weak, badly in need of medical help and care, later even succumbing to death because of these wounds. But Strauss persuasively argues that it would be impossible for such an individual to have convinced the disciples that he was the Conqueror of death, the Victor over the grave or the Prince of Life. If Jesus did not die on the cross, he could only have convinced his followers that he was someone to be pitied and cared for by them. They would have immediately perceived the facts as they were in reality. At any rate, Jesus' condition could not have changed the disciples' sorrow into happiness. Not would it have convinced them to worship Jesus as the Messiah.[23] Strauss' criticism is a very pointed and accurate one. As we noted above, Paulus did indeed conceive of Jesus as a victim of blood-letting, one whose appearance was changed due to tremendous suffering an who still felt weak and sickly, finally dying of the wounds.[24] And this is just how a survivor of a crucifixion would appear. But


122

could such a limping, bleeding, stoop-shouldered individual convince even his loved ones that he had conquered death forever? The answer is obviously a negative one.

Most theologians have therefore agreed that Strauss' critique has settled the issue for good.[25] Indeed, Schweitzer even judged that Strauss' reasoning was the absolute death stroke to the swoon theory.[26] Renan was also careful to point out the assurance we have of Jesus' death on the cross.[27]

The New Testament records claims that Jesus was nailed to the cross (Luke 24:39-40; John 20:25-27). It this could be shown to be valid, Strauss' view would be strengthened all the more.[28] And we do find, in fact, that Strauss' critique has received striking archaeological confirmation in recent years. Paul Maier reports the following:

…in the summer of 1968, archaeologist V. Tzaferis excavated some stone ossuaries in East Jerusalem dating from the first century A.D. These were chests in which bones of the dead were reburied after the flesh had decomposed following original burial in a cave. One of the ossuaries, inscribed with the name Yohanan Ben Ha' galgol, contained the bones of a man who had obviously been crucified, the first such victim ever discovered. A large, rusty iron spike, seven inches long, had been driven through both heel bones after


123

first penetrating an acacia wood wedge or plague that held the ankles firmly to the cross. The nail must have encountered a knot on being driven into the cross. The nail must have encountered a knot on being driven into the cross, for the point of the spike had been bent directly backward. Silvers still clinging to it show that the cross was made of olive wood….In addition to the iron spike, evidence of crucifixion included a deep scratch on the right radius bone of his lower forearm just above the wrist, which abraded them as the victim writhed in agony….Yohanan at any rate, had his lower arms pierced with nails…[29]

This is indeed important evidence bearing on this question. Maier further corroborates this evidence with three photographs which plainly show the affected bones of this victim. One displays a hind view of the heel bones as they were found, pierced by a large iron spike. The end of the spike is curved upwards. A second photograph reveals the portion of the right arm where the radius bone was scared by another nail. The third photograph displays a side view of the left heel bone after the spike had been removed, clearly showing the very large hole thus created by the wound.[30]

Strauss' critique of the swoon theory therefore appears to be even stronger. There is no reason to doubt the New Testament accounts of the nail wounds inflicted upon Jesus, especially in light of this archaeological evidence.

It is possible to adduce other considerations against the swoon theory as well. For instance, secondly, there is strong evidence


124

to demonstrate that Jesus was dead prior to the burial. We are told in John 19:31-35 that the legs of the other two crucified men were broken in order to hasten their deaths.[31] But since Jesus was found to be already dead, his legs were not broken. Rather a Roman soldier pierced his chest with a spear in order to make sure that he was not simply feigning it. This portion has both long and often been recognized as a proof that Jesus was dead by many scholar of differing theological positions. The general tendency by those who prefer this approach is to perceive this spear wound and the subsequent appearance of blood and water as signifying one of two medical explanations. It is thought either that the spear punctured the heart via the pericardium (a thin sac surrounding the heart, which contains a watery liquid be filled with blood and fluid). In either case the pericardium would be filled with blood and fluid). In either case the presence of both blood and water is medically explained and Jesus would have been dead.[32] The question here concerns whether this account in John is a reliable testimony as to crucifixion procedure.

Again we find some corroboration of these facts in the archaeological evidence already supplied by Maier. The bones of the crucified victim bring evidence to bear that this account of the spear wound and breaking of the legs is also based on historical


125

information (as claimed in John 19:35). Maier relates that:

Even the detail of the two criminals having their legs broken at the close of Good Friday to induce death--the crurifragium has an exact parallel here: Yohanan's right tibia and the left tibia and fibula were all broken in their lowest third segment at the same level, indicating a common crushing blow, probably from a mallet or sledge (Italics are Maier's).[33]

Now it is true that this evidence does not mention a spear wound. But once the custom of breaking the legs of the criminals has been established, it is a short step to this next point. After all, the object of each was to insure the victim's death. If one was found to be already dead, the logical thing to do would be to make sure. The spear, being a natural part of the Roman military repertoire, would be the most likely weapon. And where could one more likely kill a person with a spear than by piercing his heart? The Romans were responsible for making sure that the victim was dead, as he had been sentenced by a Roman official, and they were very efficient in such tasks.[34]

In addition, since at least this first portion of his gospel statement had been verified, there is no sufficient reason to assert that the interrelated item of the spear wound was not also historical. The two belong together, because if Jesus had not been pierced, he would most likely have had his ankles smashed as well. Both meant that he died. The best conclusion is that both are fact.

A third great difficulty for this theory is that Jesus would have to have been an impostor of one sort or another. He would


126

have been guilty of proclaiming his resurrection when such would clearly not have been the case. He, of all people, would certainly know the facts.[35] To honestly ignore them would be to make himself worse than an impostor, as it would then most likely entail some sort of mental insanity. Yet, the world almost unanimously views Jesus at least as a great moral teacher, in all probability incapable of such a grand example of deceiving others. Whatever else might be postulated, he cannot be found to be such an impostor.

Thus the swoon theory fails as an adequate explanation of the facts. Other points could also be made against it.[36] But suffice it to say that there is very little doubt among scholars today that Jesus was actually dead.[37] First, as pointed out by Strauss, he could not have convinced his disciples that he had conquered death and was victor over the grave in his physical condition. They would have known immediately that he needed medical help, not that he was immortal. Second, the facts point strongly to his actual physical death on the cross, which occurred no later than the time of the spear wound (and actually before this time). Third, Jesus was certainly not an impostor of this sort.

It is therefore no wonder that the swoon theory appeared short-lived in its popularity. By 1908 Scottish theologian James Orr could remark that no one held this view any longer.[38] Similarly,


127

today this view is also rejected as being outdated and insufficient to account for the facts at hand.[39] Frank Morison could even assert that the swoon theory is today best regarded as a theological curiosity of the past.[40]

B. David Strauss

As noted above, Strauss was one of nineteenth century liberalism's most ardent New Testament critics. His life of Jesus appeared in 1835 and occasioned a great theological furor. One result of this work was the immediate signaling of a raging battle concerning the nature of myth in the New Testament accounts.[41] A second result was Strauss' dismissal from his teaching post at Tubingen because of the radical nature of his work. Large amounts of criticism directed towards his theories were to follow, as much printed material opposed his efforts. One book even humorously demythologized David Strauss himself![42]


128

One element of the New Testament which was clearly rejected by Strauss was the accounts of miracles. Ever since David Hume's essay on miracles, these occurrences could no loner be thought to be possible. Miracles cannot break the laws of nature. Explanations other than the Biblical ones must be found.[43]

Concerning the resurrection of Jesus, Strauss is most explicit. Jesus was definitely dead and thus the swoon theory is inapplicable here.[44] Rather, Strauss preferred and popularized the subjective vision theory of the resurrection. According to this view Mary Magdalene was probably the first to perceive psychological visions of the risen Christ. Next the apostles also had subjective visions convincing them that Jesus was indeed alive.[45]

However, Strauss explains, the disciples were not in the proper frame of mind to be open to visions immediately after the death of Jesus or for even days afterwards. They were too despondent to have any hope at all so soon. Therefore both a change of locality is needed (away from Jerusalem) and a period of "recovery" before the visions could begin. Strauss thus transfers the disciples' first apparitions to Galilee in the north. The time which passed before fir first "appearance" is also expanded to a much longer period than is stated in the New Testament narratives.[46]


129

The result was internal visions which occurred because of the presence of fervent imagination and much excitement.[47] Because of this deception on the part of the disciples when they mistook their subjective experiences for the objective reality, Strauss asserts that the resurrection experiences itself has therefore become a world-wide illusion.[48]

This theory which Strauss developed gained popularity in the nineteenth century. Scholars such as Renan and Ghillany, among others, preferred it as the most probable explanation for the appearances of Jesus.[49] Its popularity has diminished in the twentieth century.[50]


130

However, several of the nineteenth century liberals opposed this view as well. Schleiermacher asserted that nay version of the vision theory was entirely unacceptable because its suppositions do not fit the facts.[51] Another rejection of this theory was given by Paulus, whose own views we have discussed above. He likewise felt that visions were not possible in view of the available facts, for there was sufficient evidence to prove that Jesus was actually alive and present with the apostles.[52] Therefore he preferred the swoon theory. This rejection of visions by Paulus is a very interesting one, because we have already out that Strauss had likewise ruled out Paulus' theory. Thus we see that each attempted to negate the theory of the other.

The most noteworthy nineteenth century criticism of Strauss' vision theory came from another liberal theologian, Theodor Keim. Schweitzer notes that Keim's study of Jesus' like, which was published in three volumes from 1867-1872, was the most important critical work on this subject that had appeared in many years.[53] In it he presented a substantial critique of all hypotheses which made subjective visions and inner experiences the basis for the disciples' belief in objective, outward appearances of Jesus.

Keim rejected the vision theory for several key reasons. First, the over-abundance of self-generated emotion and excitement which Strauss felt had to be present[54] to produce these visions is not


131

found in the early church. Other inward experiences and visions found in the early texts are likewise not characterized by this extreme excitement. Second, visions in the New Testament are numerous. But these are never confused with the resurrection appearances, so as to admit the difference between them. Third, the appearances of Jesus are characterized by calmness and reticence. Those involved are usually reserved and not at first ready to accept Jesus with joy and exuberance. Fourth, religious visions tend to multiply and grow more numerous. But the appearances of Jesus come to sudden cessation. For these and similar reasons, this theory is rejected as not adequately explaining how the appearances of Jesus could possibly have been subjective visions.[55] Some of Keim's


132

points are well well-taken and are still employed today as negative evidence that opposes this theory, as we will perceive presently. At any rate, many scholars believe that Keim dealt the death-blow to Strauss' theory of visions, just as Strauss had earlier done the same to Paulus' hypothesis.[56]

Today there are at least four major reasons why the subjective vision theory is rejected. First, the apostles were not in the proper frame of mind to presuppose visions. There is a needed psychological precondition for such hallucinations, this being the expectation of the event in question and a strong belief that it will happen. Otherwise there would be no impetus for the mind to produce such subjective projections.[57] But the disciples were not in such a state of mind. They were very despondent and did not have such faith and expectation that Jesus would rise. Pannenberg expresses this point as follow:

To maintain, first, that the appearances were produced b the enthusiastically excited imagination of the disciples does not hold, at least for the first and most fundamental appearances. The Easter faith of the disciples; rather, conversely, the Easter faith of the disciples is to be explained from the appearances. All the attempted constructions as to how the faith of the disciples could have survived the crisis of Jesus' death remain problematic precisely in psychological terms, even when one takes into account the firm expectation of the imminent end of the world with which Jesus presumably died and in which his disciples lived. It cannot be disputed that, in spite of all this, Jesus' death exposed the faith of the disciples to the most severe stress. One could hardly


133

expect the production of confirmatory experiences from the faith of the disciples that stood under such a burden. Certainly such psychological considerations by themselves are as little suited to support any conclusions as to support the criticism of the New Testament traditions.[58]

As Pannenberg clearly states here, it is psychologically problematical to endeavor to explain how the disciples' faith could have withstood the stress placed upon it by the death of Jesus. We could not expect the collective forlorn faith of these men to respond positively by producing visions which, by their nature, require enthusiasm, excitement and especially belief. Therefore we find that the appearances of Jesus gave rise to the post-Easter faith and were not produced by an already-existing faith.[59]

This position is well-attested by various others as well. Eminent Scripture scholar Raymond E. Brown notes that most theologians also agree that faith in the resurrection of Jesus arose because of the appearances rather than the appearances being caused by a pre-existing faith.[60] An examination of the facts will show that this is the case, thus making visions an impossibility.

The disciples were simply too despondent to have produced such hallucinations, especially in so short of a time. Even Marxsen realizes that the disciples' faith was a result of external experiences and not inward impulses, thus making the vision theory untenable.[61] William Barclay agrees that the disciples could not contemplate


134

themselves into a situation where visions would be possible so soon. Therefore this theory itself is perceived to by unreasonable.[62] Ramsey likewise asserts that any theory which proclaims that the resurrection appearance arose because of prior belief of the disciples, as this theory does, can be dismissed because of the problems involved.[63]

It is not overly difficult to comprehend this criticism raised against Strauss' subjective vision theory. The disciples had expected Jesus to redeem Israel and bring in the heavenly Kingdom of God (see Like 24:21). They had followed him for a few years, expecting this result. But now his death was unexpected and caused must despondency. Such a reaction is a natural psychological response when so much was at stake and believed to be dependent upon Jesus' remaining alive. Their long-awaited hopes and dreams were dashed to pieces. To expect and ecstatic, enthusiastic faith-affirmation capable of producing inward visions from these men is therefore not very possible.

An interesting concession here was made by Strauss, who also realized that, as the facts stand, visions would not have occurred. The disciples could not have escaped such despondency in such a short period of time. Thus, unless one rearranged the available data, the theory would fall.[64]


135

Therefore we find that the disciples were too despondent to have been subject to such excited visions entailing a believing frame of mind. As Marxsen concludes, we must reject the vision theory because it does not agree with the textual facts.[65] McNaugher reminds us that such hallucinations have psychological rules and these had not been fulfilled.[66]

In addition, we find that the disciples did not expect Jesus to rise from the dead.[67] Ramsey notes that they were not able to anticipate this event at all because of their aforementioned doubt and bewilderment.[68]

In fact, the disciples did not believe immediately even after the appearances, but doubted the evidence.[69] Orr believes that this doubt on the part of the disciples is the most historical portion if the resurrection records.[70] Reginald Fuller finds this doubt to be a part of the earliest tradition and a very natural inclination for these early witnesses.[71] Both Marxsen[72] and Ramsey[73] note the


136

affect of this doubt on the disciples. It is important to realize here that if the vision theory were true, such persistent doubt could not exist, because the supposed presence of the pre-existent faith would mean that the appearances would have already been regarded as genuine. In other words, if the disciples' faith in a risen Jesus had produced visions, this same faith would automatically accept the resulting visions as true. But we find that such was not the case. The doubt was both genuine and persistent.

Thus we see that, first, the disciples were not in the proper frame of mind for visions to occur. They were too despondent to have had hallucinations in so short a time.[74] In addition, they not expect Jesus to rise and did not readily believe the appearances even after they occurred. The second main reason that the vision theory is rejected is because of the problems involved concerning the number of people who claimed to have seen Jesus after his death and the different places and times in which these appearances were believed to have taken place. It is true that visions can be experienced by more than one person at a time.[75] But we have been speaking of a theory which proposes


137

subjective hallucinations--visions with no real objective stimulus. Therefore if one of the disciples (or others who claimed to have experienced the resurrection appearances) actually did hallucinate, it would not by any means be automatic that others would also experience the same vision. Rather, each would also have to go through the process of developing a prior faith and of being psychologically ready for such an experience. This is because hallucinations are essentially private events and are experienced by more than one person only when these above conditions are present for each individual.[76] But, as Pannenberg notes, the narratives record several different appearances which occur under many different circumstances and times and even include different participants. This invalidates this theory which relies upon a mental reaction which spread from one individual to the next. The various conditions simply do not support such a view.[77]

The above objections are persuasive especially when on remembers that in order for this theory to be valid, each individual would have to have responded to personal stimuli at each of these various times and places. The different personalities involved would mean that many would not be in the proper state of mind, especially when all the records indicate that exactly the opposite reaction prevailed, as shown above.


138

Surely some of the participants would not have experienced these appearances at all if they were due to visions, for they would not all be in the correct state of mind. But such was not the case. Even New Testament critics are agreed that all the disciples genuinely believed that Jesus had appeared to them after his death. In other words, whatever may have been the cause of the appearances, the disciples believed that Jesus had been raised from the dead.[78] In fact, Johannes Weiss pointed out that the early proclamation of the resurrection would not have been possible at all had the disciples experienced even the simplest doubt in an objective resurrection.[79] This undoubting belief would hardly be the consequence if we were to rely on visions to such large numbers of people as are recorded in the narratives. As mentioned above, all would not be prepared for such visions.

An instance where this would be true occurs in the oldest resurrection narrative. Here Paul relates that on one occasion Jesus appeared to over 500 people at once (I Cor. 15:6). That Paul cites this as a proof of Jesus' resurrection is evidence from his further explanation that most of these 500 witnesses were still alive at the time of his writing (and thus available to testify of the reality of this event).[80] As Brown asserts. It is hardly possible


139

to imagine a synchronized but personal experience which would convince each that Jesus had objectively risen.[81] A collective hallucination in which all saw visions would be to ignore the above-mentioned evidence to the contrary.

Another instance where the vision theory appears especially improbable is Luke's recording of the walk to Emmaus (Luke 24:13-33). This narrative, complete with proper names (such as Cleopas, Emmaus and Jerusalem), convinced Martin Dibelius that the pure form of the event had been preserved at this point.[82] This incident has received much respect from critics who have rejected other aspects of the resurrection accounts.[83] Here we find that the shifting scenes, continual conversation and the time element involved all militate strongly against the reality of visions.[84] Paul's list of appearances in I Cor. 15:1-8 is also quite problematical for his viewpoint as well.[85]

It would be advantageous here to recall two of Keim's criticisms made last century which were discussed above. First, appearances of Jesus and visions which occur at later times (such as II Cor. 12:2-4; Acts


140

7:55-56; 18:9; 23:11; 27:23).[86] This would not be the case if the resurrection appearances were of the same variety as the later visions, as all would viewed as being of the same type. This is an acute point because it demonstrates that the resurrection experiences were regarded as being unique and were therefore not of a subjective visional character.[87] Second, if these appearances of the risen Jesus had not been perceived to be unique, then one would not expect them to have ceased so suddenly. Rather, they would tend to have been related to the later visions. That they did stop indicates that the early church did not want them to be confused with spiritual visions.[88]

Therefore we perceive once again the second chief criticism of the vision theory. Many factors have contributed to this probability that the number of visions, the number of people who saw them and the way in which these occurred simply do not correspond to the required data for the disciples to have experienced such manifestations.

The third major criticism of this theory is that real subjective hallucinations are comparatively rare, as proper causes are usually lacking. They are, by definition, experiences in which something is perceiving to be present, but for which there is no objective reality. Thus they differ from illusions, where a reality is mistakenly identified.[89] Thus it can be ascertained that such occurrences are


141

generally rare. The perception of something that not only is not present but for which there is no objective reality at all therefore requires an explanation. Usually such hallucinations are caused by mental illness of some kind, drugs or extreme methods of bodily deprivation.[90] To suppose that all of the witnesses of the resurrection appearances were in such a state of mind thus becomes nonfactual. We can now better understand how an extreme pre-conditioned hope and expectation must exist in order for all of the disciples to imagine something that was only "thin air".[91] Therefore Pannenberg rightly concludes that to describe the resurrection appearances as hallucinations or subjective visions is completely unsatisfactory.[92]

The fourth major reason why the vision theory is rejected today (and the last which we will deal with specifically) is that cautions were actually taken in order to demonstrate that the appearances were not hallucinations. We have already conviction of contemporary scholars that the disciples were convinced that Jesus was actually alive only after the appearances and not before.[93] We have likewise


142

spoken of the conviction of the New Testament author that the appearances of the risen Jesus were different from later visions. Reginald Fuller especially notes here that Paul did not confuse these appearances with the subjective visions which were experienced later.[94]

In addition, we find that other steps were also taken to disprove visions as the origin of the appearances. We find these "safeguards" in both the earlier and the later narratives which deal with this subject. The emphasis in Matthew, Luke-Acts and John on Jesus' resurrection body being both spiritual and material is well-known.[95] We find an emphasis on being able to see and handle the body of Jesus. In Luke especially it is related that it occurred to the disciples that they were seeing just such a spiritual hallucination--a bodiless apparition.[96] Although these gospels were written later than Paul's description of the resurrection appearances, it is recognized by many scholars that the description of Jesus' body in the gospels may have been derived, at least in part, from the same source as Paul's conception of a "spiritual body". In other words, it is often recognized that both Paul and the gospels


143

speak of a resurrection body composed of both spiritual and material qualities (with varying emphases) and that these concepts were in turn based on the reports of the original eyewitnesses.[97]

What is often not realized is that Paul's list of appearances in I Cor. 15:1-8 also contains a polemic against theories such as that of subjective visions. As Brown properly notes, Paul's reference to 500 people having seen Jesus at one time means Paul conceived of the appearances as being other than purely internal experiences. Thus hallucinations were not possible in view of his testimony.[98] This is especially true when we remember that Paul adds that most of these witnesses were still alive and thus could be questioned. Therefore, this testimony in I Cor. 15:6 is regarded by Paul himself as proof against subjective visions.[99]

Thus we see that there were precautions taken in both Paul's account and in the gospels guar against the view that the appearances were due to subjective visions and therefore not genuine. This motif is more developed in the gospels, where we are told that Jesus body was touched on various occasions, demonstrating its reality.[100] But we have seen how Paul also includes also includes a proof against


144

such a theory as well.[101] That this is the case in the New Testament is only natural when we consider man's psychological impulse to investigate both strange occurrences ad the testimony of others who claim to have experienced such.[102]

Therefore we perceive that the vision theory cannot account for the resurrection appearances of Jesus. Several major points militate against such a view. The disciples were not in the correct psychological frame of mind. There is also a problem concerning the number who claim to have seen Jesus and the time place factors involved. In addition, real hallucinations and visions are rare and do not fit the facts. Lastly, the early sources explain that carious cautions were taken to prove that visions were not applicable in these instances. Many minor points could also be mentioned against this theory.[103] Most of these objections can also be applied theories relying upon other subjective experiences of the apostles as well.[104]


145

We thus conclude that the visional theory simply does not fit the narratives. For hallucinations to have occurred, all of the facts must be changed around. There are psychological laws which these hallucinations must abide by and these were not present.[105] No matter how inviting a theory may appear, if it fails to account for the evidence, it must be rejected.[106]

Today vision theory is held by comparatively few scholars. Brown notes that this nineteenth century view is not even respectable any longer.[107] Based upon the fear and dejection of the disciples, Bornkamm asserts that we cannot resort to any explanation which depends upon the inner, subjective experience of these men.[108] McLeman agrees that the nineteenth century vision theorists such as Strauss and Renan presented views which were quite extravagant in their claims.[109] Even Schonfield rejects this theory as not fitting the evidence. Whatever theory may be proposed, it cannot validly be this one.[110]


146

C. Otto Pfleiderer

In the last portion of the nineteenth century a movement appeared from within the ranks of Protestant liberalism. It became designated as the History of Religions school of thought. It opposed several if liberalism's suppositions, such as trying to find a "Jesus of history". In fact, it was believed that very little historical information could be gathered about the life of Jesus.[111] This was mainly due to the legendary growth which was said to have built up around the life of Christ. These legends were believed to have accumulated in stages until the embellished material became detailed.[112]

The History of Religions school sought to study Christianity in terms of the other religions. The Christian faith came to be seen as being syncretistic and therefore it was not unique in the sense that it did borrow from the other faiths. It was now postulated by these scholars that Christianity borrowed quite freely from Judaism and from other systems of belief such as the Babylonian, Egyptian and Persian religions.[113] It was postulated that Christianity was especially influenced by the Old Testament and by the teachings of these other faiths. Myths were believed to be extremely prevalent at this time and were perceived to be spreading from one region and religion to another. Each then accepted ideas from other that


147

were advantageous to its own purposes. As a result, these scholars constantly compared almost every individual category of the Christian faith to similar ideas which were a part of other religions.[114]

One scholar who had many beliefs in common with this emerging school of thought was German theologian Otto Pfleiderer. For instance, he also postulated that there were many affinities between Christianity and other ancient religions. The influence from Judaism was also noteworthy. Myths were said to be present in all of these faiths and there were similarities, especially in the transmission of events requiring Supernatural intervention. Especially noticeable is Pfleiderer's tendency to compare different aspects of the Christian faith with similar ideas and occurrences in these other religions. Parallels are found, for instance, in Jesus' relationship to Satan, in the miracles of Jesus, and in the accounts of the resurrection.[115]

Pfleiderer also believed that very little could be known about the beginnings of the Christian faith. He likewise based this conclusion upon the thesis that legends grew profusely around the life of Jesus in the early church. It is now too difficult to know for sure which reported events actually occurred and which did not.[116]


148

The History of Religions school rejected any belief in the resurrection of Jesus. Rather, they popularized the view that the narratives of this occurrence were later additions to the gospel, ones which grew mainly from the influence of stories of other such events found in other religions. At any rate, the resurrection was considered to be a legend which was added to the story of Jesus' life.[117]

Pfleiderer follows this pattern and also views the resurrection of Jesus as myth that did not occur literally. But he does so for two main reasons. First, the resurrection is believed to be legend added to the story of Jesus' life by his earliest followers. It was not a real occurrence at all, for Jesus never actually rose from the dead. Rather, the narratives were added by the disciples, who were convinced that Jesus must be alive. The legends continued to grow until they were detailed account of a victory over death. In addition, stories of resurrected gods in other religions served as a basis for the rise of the Christian legends about Jesus. These more ancient myths provided the impetus from the formulation of the New Testament accounts of Jesus rising from the dead.[118]

Second, Pfleiderer believes that this theory based upon the formation of legends must also be supplemented by the subjective vision theory o the resurrection.[119] Visions apparently account


149

for the source of the conviction that Jesus was alive, while the subsequent legends explain the present form of the narratives.[120] We have already dismissed the vision theory above, and we will turn presently to the possibility that the narratives are due to legends. We will henceforth refer to this hypothesis as the mythical or legendary theory of the resurrection.

Even in the twentieth century the mythical or legendary theory of the resurrection can be found.[121] Probably the best-known theologian today who advocates a somewhat related form of this theory is Rudolf Bultmann.[122] He freely recognizes his indebtness to the History of Religions school of thought, especially in his understanding of the meaning of myth. For Bultmann, New Testament mythology is made up of elements quite similar to concept found in both Jewish apocalypticism and the redemption myths of gnosticism.[123] All have several features in common. As a result, we find that many of the gospel miracles, for instance, are close to those in the Hellenistic


150

narratives. Bultmann draws parallels between some of these gospel miracles and those of other ancient peoples in a way much reminiscent of Pfleiderer's attempt spoken of above.[124]

Also similar to Pfleiderer is Bultmann's twofold treatment of the resurrection. First, there is a stress on the presence of legendary material in the New Testament accounts. For instance, this event is viewed as being a myth which was constructed by imagination and legend.[125] But second, while in his discussion of the resurrection Bultmann laid much more emphasis on the part played by this legendary growth, it is noteworthy that he also felt that the vision theory was also a very possible explanation, at least in part.[126] While the narratives of Jesus' rising from the dead do have significance when we view them as being pointers to the uniqueness of Jesus' death, the resurrection of nonetheless a myth devoid of historical reality and thus not an actual historical event.[127]

For Bultmann, the New Testament church combined and mingled Greek and Jewish (Old Testament) mythology.[128] It is no surprise, therefore,


151

that this scholar postulated that the resurrection also had similarities to beliefs in other religions and systems of thought. The affect of such beliefs upon this Christian doctrine of a risen Jesus might partially be realized, for instance, in Paul's speaking of the resurrection in gnostic terms.[129] The gnostic influence on such narratives is also found in other portions of the New Testament.[130] Bultmann holds that Jewish sources also influenced the faith that the early church had in Jesus' resurrection. Old Testament verses were reinterpreted as predictions of this event. In fact, one of the early proof of this occurrence was what the Christians felt was just such Jewish Scriptural support.[131] We therefore find that certain aspects of the New Testament's teaching about the resurrection were influenced by other ancient faith systems. As a result of these and other legendary features involved in the Christian faith, little can actually be known about the historical Jesus with any degree of certainty.[132]

Earlier we saw how nineteenth century liberal theology as a whole followed Hume in its rejection of miracles.[133] We should also note that Pfleiderer was no exception here. He likewise accepted the


152

view that science had discovered the laws of nature which were so regular that they could not be violated.[134] Even in the twentieth century this view was accepted by Bultmann (as shown above), who rejected the miraculous both because it was perceived to contradict the laws of nature and because we live in too modern of an age to accept such occurrences as fact.[135]

It is apparent that there are several similarities between Bultmann and Pfleiderer on the concept of mythology, especially with regard to the treatment of the resurrection. Therefore Bultmann's position will also be included in the discussion and critique in this section.

We will turn now to an examination of what we will term the legendary or mythical theory of the resurrection of Jesus.[136] Ancient mythology relates various tales concerning "vegetation gods". In their earlier forms these stories, in other words, celebrated the yearly death of vegetation during the fall season and the birth of the vegetation in the spring season. These myths originally dealt only with an expression of man's observances of this yearly cycle of vegetation. Later they were transformed into narratives expressing religious beliefs about the gods.[137]


153

Various versions of such myths circulated around the ancient would. The details vary from culture to culture, but they do appear to have the most prominent features more-or-les in common, as they revolved mainly around the death of a vegetation god. The god is in love with a goddess but becomes separated from his lover, often by death. She usually mourns for him and sometimes receives him back into the land of the living.[138] The Summerian form of this myth concerns the god Dumuzi and the goddess Inanna.[139] The Babylonian version is about Tammuz and Ishtar.[140] The Egyptian rendering speaks of Osiris and Isis.[141] Other cultures depict their gods and goddesses directly patterned upon these major versions. For instance, Phoenician mythology presents Adonis and Astarte and Phrygian mythology concerns Attis and Cybele, both of which are the equivalent of the Babylonian Tammuz and Istar.[142] The Greek equivalent of the Egyptian god Osiris is Dionysus.[143]

It is generally asserted by those who hold the legend theory that these myths concerning the vegetation gods not only permeated Christian circles, but that they formed the basis for the Christian belief in the resurrection of Jesus. The foundation thus laid by the influence of these ancient myths then is believed to have provided


154

the framework for later legendary accumulations, which continued to grow.[144]

There are at least four major reasons (and several addition minor ones) as to why the legend theory of the resurrection attracts the attention of comparatively few scholars today. First, there is ample proof from contemporary theological studies that Jesus' resurrection lies at the very roots of New Testament belief. In other words, it is not simply a flattering tale added to the origins of Christianity years after the death of Jesus.

It is agreed by al that Paul's account of the resurrection in I Cor. 15:3-8 is the earliest witness to this occurrence. It is also almost entirely unanimous that Paul is not passing on material which he has formulated himself, but rather is citing a much earlier tradition.[145] In other words, the earliest account of the resurrection appearances was formulated before Paul actually wrote this book and thus it is earlier than the composition of the book in which it appears.[146]

The key question is how near this ancient formulation of these appearances is to the actual events. Pannenberg believes that the creed is quite close to the original appearances of Jesus.[147] Most others agree with him for several agree with him for several reasons. First, Paul's words "I


155

delivered" and "I received" are technical jargon referring to the Jewish custom of the transmission of ancient data.[148] Second, there are words in this portion which are non-Pauline, pointing to an earlier formulation by others.[149] Third, at least Jeremias believes that the origin of these words is Aramaic and not Greek, thus dating back to the earliest sources.[150]

For these and other similar reasons, it is the belief of most theologians today that this formulation reported by Paul is about as close to the original appearances as is possible for such a formalized creed. This is because a little time would be required for this process of formalization into a list of appearances. We do not know if Paul preserved the list exactly in its original form or if he added to it or modified it, but the core material concerning the appearances of Jesus dates to just a short time after Jesus' death.[151]

In all likelihood, Paul received this information about Jesus' resurrection from Peter and James when he visited Jerusalem after his conversion (Gal. 1:18-19).[152] This is especially likely when we remember that there are single appearances of Jesus to both Peter


156

and James in this early traditional formulation (I Cor. 15:5, 7). Therefore, Reginald Fuller states that the very latest that this list could have been formulated would be five years after the original appearances, or about 35 A.D. when Paul made this visit to Jerusalem.[153] Pannenberg dates the visit and the subsequent receiving of this information as occurring sic to eight years after these events.[154] But Fuller rightly notes that this is the latest that the tradition could have been formulated (so that Paul could have received it at that time). It very well could have crystallized much earlier.

Therefore, we find that the disciples taught the resurrection of Jesus from the very beginning. There was no period of inactivity when this was not their contral theme for preaching.[155] The early formulated cited by p=Paul demonstrates that the proclamation of the resurrection rests upon the testimony of the original eye witnesses and not upon a legendary process. Therefore this carefully-worded tradition in I. Cor. 15:3-8 reveals explicitly that the appearances of Christ were experienced by groups of early Christians and not invented as a part of later legendary development. This early date caused Pannenberg to conclude that:

Under such circumstances it is an idle venture to make parallels in the history of religions responsible for the emergence of the primitive Christian message about Jesus' resurrection (Italics are Pannenberg's).[156]


157

Thus we see, first of all, that myths in ancient religions in all probability cannot be made to account for the rise of the belief in Jesus' resurrection from the dead because the New Testament accounts are simply too close to the events themselves to be legends, as we have seen here.[157]

The second reason that the legend or myth theory is rejected is in some ways to the first. In addition to the very early date given to the earliest tradition which reports the appearances of the resurrected Jesus, we are informed that we have the testimony of eyewitnesses to this fact. Above we discussed the probability that two of the original persons to whom Jesus appeared, Peter and James, were the one who had passed this information to Paul. But there is additional New Testament evidence that must now be discussed which demonstrates that the original eyewitnesses agreed with Paul in teaching that Jesus both rose from the dead and that he appeared to them. To show that such eyewitnesses also believed and taught that this event occurred after Jesus' death and that they witnessed the appearances would of course be an extremely strong point against the legend theory. We will deal more with this below, showing why this point is so acute.

In I Cor. 15 we have not only the earliest testimony concerning Jesus' resurrection appearances to the apostles and to others (vs. 1-8), but we also have Paul's statement that these same apostles also preached these same facts. Paul thereby asserts that the message which he was preaching about the resurrection appearances was the same as that to which the other apostles were also testifying (I Cor. 15:11).[158] Later he mentions three times that these original


158

eyewitnesses to the appearances were also preaching of their experiences with the risen Jesus (I Cor. 15:14, 15). Even the critics admit that Paul is here witnessing to the content of the early disciples' message--that both Paul and these other eyewitnesses were proclaiming a risen Lord who had appeared to them.[159] In other words, those who had seen the risen Lord were now relating this to others. And they did so immediately after the events occurred. Paul additionally explains that the 500 who had also beheld an appearance of the Lord, while they perhaps were not themselves actively preaching about their experiences, were still available for questioning, as most of them were still living (I Cor. 15:6). Therefore we see that a number of eyewitnesses were either preaching or were available for questioning concerning their experiencing of various appearances of the risen Jesus. This testimony did not take place only years later, but immediately after the original manifestations.

We also receive confirmation of Paul's testimony in the gospels and the book of Acts. Although some critical scholars do not believe that any eyewitnesses were the authors of any of the four gospels, most believe that at the very least some can be traced to eyewitness testimony. Therefore we can at least say that, in all probability, Mark received much material from the apostles Peter, Matthew from the apostles Matthew, Luke-Acts from various eyewitnesses (Luke 1:1-4) and John from the apostles John.[160] These, then also point to


159

eyewitness testimony concerning the resurrection appearances of Jesus

The importance of eyewitness testimony such as this is hard to over-estimate. We have seen how virtually all agree that the earliest church, including those who were the original observers, proclaimed Jesus' resurrection from the dead.[161] That these first witnesses did not simply fraudulently invent the narratives, fully believing that Jesus was still dead, is evidence and admitted by all. Men do not risk their lives and even die[162] for what they know to be


160

only a fabricated falsehood. Also, as J.N.D. Anderson points out, the quality of the ethical teaching of the early disciples and the fact that none ever recanted under the threat of losing their lives further repudiates any theory based upon such fraud. In addition, the psychological transformation of the disciples is left unaccounted for if they invented the stories.[163] Thus they actually believed that Jesus had risen from the dead.[164]

But under these conditions the legend theory is impossible. This is obvious not only because those who witnessed the appearances proclaimed the exact opposite. Of course, proclaiming something does not necessarily make it true. But since we have ruled out any chances of a fabricated story or lie on the part of the disciples,[165] there


161

has to be a reason why these men would come to believe that Jesus had risen from the dead. The other leading theories (the swoon and vision theories) have also failed as adequate solutions, as shown above. Therefore these cannot be used as the impetus for this faith. So the legend theory also fails because some event had to have happened at the very beginning to convict the disciples that a resurrection had actually occurred. There could have been no gradual build-up of legends because these events were reported from the very first to be true. Neither do other naturalistic theories help to explain this conviction and unquestioning belief on the part of the earliest witnesses.

To proclaim that other ancient myths are the basis for these appearances merely begs the question. To proclaim that Jesus rose because ancient mythology relates such a scheme for the so-called "vegetation gods" does not solve the problem of the origin of faith which convinced the disciples that this event had actually occurred. It also fails to account for the need of the disciples to fabricate appearances of the risen Jesus as narrated in the early formulations. They would obviously know that Jesus had not risen unless they were otherwise deceived (as by a swoon, or by visions). But the conditions for such deception are obviously lacking and this therefore renders such suppositions useless. We are thus caught in a hopeless bind.

The third major criticism of the legend of myth theory (as well as the fourth) even challenges the legend or myth theory (as well as the fourth) even challenges the supposition that any parallels at all can be drawn between the New Testament proclamation of Jesus' resurrection and the resurrection claimed for the vegetation gods of other ancient religions. The main difference between Christianity and the myths of the vegetation gods centers in the fact that Jesus


162

was a historical person, but these gods and heroes were not.[166] The person of Jesus is historically accessible, whereas those of the mythical characters such as Dumuzi, Tammuz, Osiris and the others live only in the tales spread about them. For instance, many claimed to have see the resurrection Jesus, but not so with these mythical figures.[167]

Therefore we perceive that there are no historical grounds upon which we can compare the two types of resurrection stories. Neither are there any historical grounds upon which we can compare the two types of resurrection stories. Neither are there any historical grounds upon which to compare even the lives of Jesus and of these other gods and heroes. Here we find no close connections.[168] In fact, in none of these mythical characters do we find belief in a historical resurrection from the dead as is presented in the New Testament concerning Jesus. This is an important point because it means that, far from having so many resurrection tales after which the disciples could have "patterned" Jesus' resurrection as some of these theorists would have us believe, there were no previous stories of a historical person among these vegetation gods being raised. Jesus' story is therefore unique.

The fourth major criticism against the legend or myth theory is that there is considerable doubt about just how much the teaching of resurrection is found in this ancient mythology at all. Therefore the question yet remains as to the extent that the New Testament was


163

"inspired" by the resurrection myths of other religions. For instance, Orr feels that these ancient myths are too vague and fluctuating to determine the amount of their influence. Their lack of historical reality adds to this confusion.[169]

In addition, the assumed diffusion of ideas of the resurrection of gods into Judaism and Christianity has anything but been proven. Even the critic Kirsopp Lake believed that the differently with the legend theory was in ascertaining how much based upon real fact and how much was due to overzealous guessing.[170] Pannenberg agrees that this diffusion has not been proven. In first-century Palestine there are almost no traces whatsoever of any influence from these ancient cults of resurrected gods.[171]

It was this last point that once baffled Oxford scholar C.S. Lewis when he was an atheist. After coming to accept the dependence of the New Testament upon ancient mythology, he was nonplussed by the so few times that any reference was made to any death and rebirth patterns similar to those in ancient mythologies. He also found that such elements were essentially absent from Jesus' teachings as well, which was hard to comprehend if the aforementioned influence was so great.[172]

Orr also believes that the legend theory is too arbitrary, as well. It desires to choose points of similarity while disregarding


164

differences. He feels that it is not hard to use the imagination in order to find isolated areas of agreement.[173] Pfleiderer agrees that the mistake is often made where points of difference are neglected in order to bring about a connection between the facts which are more similar.[174] An example here is appropriate. Pfleiderer himself seems to lay a certain emphasis on the myths which present the resurrection of a god on the third day.[175] but he fails to stress as much the celebration of Adonis' acclaimed resurrection on the first day after the period of mourning[176] or Attis' acclaimed resurrection on the fourth day.[177]

But even after all of these doubts, the key matter concerns the problem of the extent to which a resurrection from the dead is really found in any of these myths. For instance, the key manuscripts in the Sumerian Dumuzi-Inanna myth break off before the ending and therefore contain no account of a resurrection at all. In fact, a recent discovery of one fragment reveals that Inanna allows Dumuzi to be taken to the underworld rather than rescuing him from this realm of the dead.[178] In the Babylonian myth of Tammuz-Ishtar there is also


165

no specific mention of a resurrection. Rather, Tammuz is only inferentially (not explicitly) thought to have been raised,[179] and some even question this.[180] In addition, it has been shown that there is no sign of any resurrection in the early accounts of Adonis. The texts which refer to such an event date from no earlier than the second century A.D. and thus after the time of Christ's resurrection.[181] Likewise, the god Attis is not presented as being resurrected until after the middle of the second century A.D.[182] One early critic who preferred the legend or myth theory, P. Jensen, cited the Gilgamesh myths as providing a background for Jesus' resurrection, when these myths say nothing at all about such an occurrence.[183]

For these reasons, it is doubted just how much the idea of resurrection can be found in such ancient religion. The references that we do find are fewer than expected, somewhat ambiguous, and not enough to account for the prominence that this belief supposedly reached.[184] Therefore Yamauchi asserts that the only god for which we have both clear and early evidence (before Christ's life) of a resurrection is the Egyptian Osiris. However, this god provides no


166

inspiration for the Christian concept of resurrection, especially since Osiris is always pictured as a mummy. He did not stay on earth after his return to life, but rather descended to rule the underworld. This is a far cry from Jesus' appearances to his followers in this world. We must look elsewhere to find any inspiration for the narratives of Jesus' resurrection as depicted in the New Testament.[185]

Therefore we perceive that there is actually much less of a basis for the ancient belief in the resurrection of gods than was originally thought. A few questionable references to such occurrences do not provide the needed proof. There is especially little basis for the theory that these beliefs in other cultures were just "floating around" and that they are the foundation and background for the Christian teachings.[186]

Thus we see here a converging negative result when the legendary or mythical theory of Jesus' resurrection is examined. First, the earliest narratives concerning are too close to the events themselves to allow any time for legends to have formed at all. This is especially true of Paul's list of appearances in I Cor. 15:3-8. There was no gradual build-up of legends here. Second, the direct and indirect testimony from eyewitnesses is a very strong objection to this view. That these witnesses were not lying is


167

agreed by all, for men do not suffer tremendous discomfort and even death for what is known to be a lie. It is also agreed by all that they at least actually believed that they had really seen something. Therefore it is impossible to assume that they reported a legend or ancient myth as having actually occurred, for they would both know that they were lying when they narrated literal appearances of Jesus an they could not have actually believed that they had really seen him. Some event had to have occurred which convinced them that Jesus was risen, otherwise there would have been the need to invent the narratives. This is why this theory is usually coupled with another. A legend does not provide such realistic impetus. But the other key theories (swoon and visionary) were also found to be inadequate.

Third, there are some primary differences between the nonhistorical resurrection of vegetation gods and the resurrection of a historical person. The parallels between the two types of beliefs have very little in common. Fourth, a comparison of the New Testament narratives with the stories of these vegetation gods reveals further that the supposedly similar characteristics are usually missing. In addition, there is real doubt as to the presence of real resurrection stories in ancient mythology and the extent to which they appear. There is certainly no actual basis to believe that these myths were simply "floating around" in Jesus' time. For these and other reasons, this theory must be rejected a being inadequate to explain Jesus' resurrection.[187] As Orr asserts, it simply lacks any historical


168

foundation and relies too much on highly questionable comparisons. We cannot dismiss facts just by pointing to artificial mythical origins.[188]

Bultmann's modification of this theory also fails for similar reasons. First, his reliance on gnostic influences upon the resurrection of Jesus must be rejected for almost the same reasons as those raised above for rejecting the influences from other ancient mythologies. The comparisons are not as close as might be expected with regards to the belief in this event, as already explained. Bultmann must have realized this himself, however, because he does not try to make gnostic sources account for the basic foundation of the New Testament resurrection narratives. Rather, we have noted above that he utilizes these myths to explain periphery portions of the resurrection such as Jesus' exaltation over all cosmic powers. This does not explain the core proclamation of a risen Jesus at all and thus cannot be the basis of these claims in the earliest church.

Second, Bultmann's scientific world view is outdated. We can no longer rule out miracles a priori because of a belief in a mechanistic, closed universe that rejects the miraculous from the outset (as pointed out in chapter three above). Yet, this is what Bultmann does, as we have already seen.[189] Physicist Werner


169

Schaaffs,[190] the philosopher Gordon Clark[191] both agree in this criticism. Miracles cannot be excluded in this way because of the modern scientific world in which we live today. Such an approach in not valid.

Third, theologian John Macquarrie also criticizes Bultmann for his arbitrary dismissal for the resurrection without any investigation whatsoever,[192] due to his lack of studying the historical evidence. As with Hume, just such an investigation may have revealed the resurrection to be a probable event. Macquarrie also notes the defective scientific view involved.[193]

These second and third criticisms are very substantial ones indeed. They are some of the strongest arguments against Bultmann, who is seen as using as outdated and ineffective view of science, as well as neglecting any historical investigation at all. The resurrection Jesus can no longer be rejected for these reasons. In order to ascertain if this event has actually occurred, it must be investigated. It cannot be ruled out a priori as done by Bultmann.

In addition, Bultmann's view still falls prey especially to the first and second major criticism listed above. The earliest


170

narratives are too close to the events to refer to them simply as myths. Also, the eyewitness testimony rules out this theory. As mentioned above, to refer to the resurrection as a myth does not explain why the original disciples came to relate their experiences with the risen Jesus. Even Bultmann admits that they really believed that Jesus rose from the dead.[194] But something had to cause this belief. Myth in other religions or the development of later legends cannot account for the beginning of this belief because this is no basis from which to project the original resurrection appearances, which would otherwise be pure lies. The disciples would not have actually believed that they had seen Jesus, no matter how prominent other such stories may have been Jesus, not matter how prominent other such stories may have been (and we have seen that they were not that common). They could not therefore have believed that Jesus had actually appeared to them personally unless they had been otherwise deceived. This is probably why Bultmann suggests visions as the answer.[195] but, as we have seen, this and other such theories of deception are also quite inadequate. But legends or myths are especially inept at providing the needed impetus. Therefore Bultmann also fails in his attempt to explain away the literal resurrection of Jesus.

As pointed out by Brown, this legend of myth theory is rejected by most theologians today.[196] Bornkamm points out that there is a decisive lack of common ground between this theory and the New Testament


171

narratives.[197] Pannenberg likewise asserts that such legends cannot account for Jesus' resurrection.[198]


172

Chapter VII. Possibility Number Two: That the Resurrection Did Occur, But That it Cannot be Demonstrated

A. Soren Kierkegaard: An Introduction

The second major possibility to be dealt with is that the resurrection of Jesus did occur, but that this occurrence cannot be demonstrated. We will first examine the views of a very significant scholar who held this opinion. This theologian and philosopher, Soren Kierkegaard (1813-1855), is probably the best-known representative of this viewpoint.

Although Kierkegaard was not the first scholar to formulate a hypothesis such as this, he popularized this view in a way which was influenced twentieth century theology immensely. He has been chosen here as the primary representative of this view because of the affect which his work has exerted on many contemporary theologians. This influence is especially apparent, for instance, in this scholar's treatment of miracles. Beginning with Karl Barth's Epistle to the Romans in 1918,[1] various theological schools of thought have followed Kierkegaard in postulating that the miraculous cannot be demonstrated to have occurred in any way. This is especially true of the resurrection. The occurrence of this event is often affirmed in various


173

ways, with the understanding that there is no way that it can be verified or proven.[2] In fact, it is probable that even most of the theologians since Barth who reject any belief in a real resurrection of Jesus still manifest the influence of Kierkegaard in their belief that this event was not meant to be proven anyway. Such miracles are simply not open to objective verification.[3] We will deal with the reasoning behind such assertions below.

It is mainly for these reasons that Kierkegaard has been chosen here as the representative of this viewpoint. This Danish scholar has exercised much influence on twentieth century theology. His view of miracles was especially influential. As will be shown in the next chapter, a very large portion of contemporary theology has followed Kierkegaard in holding that miracles cannot be demonstrated, whether these occurrences are accepted as really happening or not. He is thus an excellent example of one who believes that miracles such as the resurrection did occur but that any attempts at demonstrating their validity are fruitless and misleading.

Before we proceed to an examination of Kierkegaard's view concerning miracles, it will be advantageous to look briefly at some of the intellectual background for his polemic. Perhaps more than with most other well-known thinkers, much of this scholar's thought is derived from personal experiences, such as his observation of the


174

conditions in his native land of Denmark.

Kierkegaard experienced a difficult boyhood. Apparently because of family problems and also because of a physical deformity (his back was crooked and he limped), he endured acute periods of melancholy which seemed to be continually present in his life.[4] By his own admission he suffered greatly from this daily depression, which was complicated by the conviction that he had been singled out in order to suffer for others. These emotions caused him a great amount of consternation and kept him from the real joy in life which might otherwise have been attainable.[5]

It was at least partially due to this intense melancholy and conviction that he must suffer for others that Kierkegaard encountered two other experiences which had a tremendous affect upon his life. First, he felt obliged to break off his engagement to his lover, Regina Olson. Although both loved each other very much, Kierkegaard felt that somehow the break was God's guidance and will for his life. But because he still loved her, he struggled much with his feelings. His writings reveal this battle which he waged with himself. His action seemed to be attributable to the melancholy from which he still suffered. But nonetheless, this broken engagement led to an immense amount of writing on his part. His time was now spent in


175

publishing his views on various subjects, especially theology and philosophy. His rate of production over the coming years has rarely been equalled, especially in the diversity of the subjects which were covered.[6]

Second, Kierkegaard attacked a weekly news sheet named the Corsair. This publication openly denounced many public figures, embarrassing them in the process. Kierkegaard had hoped to expose this literary tirade with the help of other prominent men of Copenhagen who also disliked the methods of this paper. But he received no help and thus suffered all of the brunt of the return attack upon himself. And the Corsair was quite vicious in its presentations of this Danish thinker, deriding him because of his physical deformity. For instance, it made light of the unequal length of his two legs. This procedure continued in the paper for approximately one year and soon he looked upon with much derision by the public. But Kierkegaard accepted this treatment as part of the suffering with was ordained for him. It caused him to become even more withdraw from society and resolved to continue the work he had begun.[7]

One conviction that Kierkegaard continued to act upon was his polemic against the presence of Hegelian-influenced theology in Denmark. The Hegelian version of Christianity encouraged people to reason clearly, as if this was all there was involved in becoming a Christian. The popular belief in Denmark was the being a good Danish


176

citizen and being a Christian were almost synonymous.[8] Kierkegaard attacked these presuppositions, pointing out that Christianity is much more than a life of easy living. Rather, it is a total transformation of the individual based upon the personal recognition of one's being a sinner. It involves a commitment to God through faith in the death of Christ to pay for one's sins. The result is the imitation of Christ.[9] In fact, the chief theme of all of his writings was to speak to those living in "Christendom" to inform them about how they could become true New Testament Christians.[10]

This brief background will make the proceeding presentation of Kierkegaard's arguments more comprehensible. After endeavoring to understand the reasoning behind this treatment of miracles, a critique of these views will then be presented in order to ascertain their ability to support Kierkegaard's arguments. It should be mentioned before passing, however, that the two main texts which will be used here are Kierkegaard's Concluding Unscientific Postscript[11] and his Philosophical Fragments.[12] This is for a few very important reasons.


177

The Danish scholar himself relates to us that the former volume is both the turning point of his work as an author and the transition between his aesthetic works and his religious ones.[13] In addition, quite a large portion of this work concerns of the main topics which is to be discussed here and other related thoughts.[14] On the other hand, the primary problem treated by the latter work concerns whether or not the Christian faith can be based on historical events[15] and this is the key question to be dealt with in this chapter. After thus perceiving these introductory facts, it is now possible to proceed to our presentation of Kierkegaard's views.

B. Soren Kierkegaard's Argument and a Critique

As a theologian and philosopher, Kierkegaard's writings were not overly popular beyond Scandinavia and Germany until the twentieth century.[16] As pointed out above, he often reacted against both the "official Christianity" of his day, which was very defective in terms


178

of the New Testament definition, and against the philosophy of Hegelianism.[17] Both trends were leading people away from real Christianity. It was at least partially as a result of his bold stand taken against these ideas that he was not very popular in his own time. However, his works were revived in this century by both secular and religious existentialism, by such scholars as Karl Barth, Martin Heidegger and Jean-Paul Sartre.[18] Today one cannot even deal adequately with existentialism without noting the influences of Kierkegaard and the impetus which he gave to the beginnings of this philosophy.[19]

Kierkegaard formulated and defended the well-known philosophical statement that "Truth is Subjectivity".[20] Therefore, while several forms of philosophy teach that the way to knowledge is to speak objective truth in one form or another this is viewed as being impossible. We can only achieve the truth by subjectivity.[21]

Do objective approaches have any validity at all? For Kierkegaard, objective reflection can yield objective truth, such as mathematics


179

and history. In other words, objective facts can be true, especially in an objective sense as with the above disciplines.[22] We might phrase this way: a rational, objective approach to reality can yield true facts, but it cannot lead to eternal truth, which is a different concept.

An example which is introduced here by this Danish thinker will serve to illustrated this point. A patient from an insane asylum succeeded in escaping from the institution. He knew that he would have to express himself sanely when he arrived in a nearby city, lest someone perceive the truth of the matter and send him back. As he walked along he picked up a ball and put it into the pocket of his coat. This continually bounced against his body against his body with every step that he took. Inspired by this, the patient began repeating to himself each time if happened, "Bang, the earth is round". When he reached the city he attempted to convince one of his friends that he was sane by speaking objectively. So he again repeated, "Bang, the earth is round". But alas, instead of being able to convince the doctor that he was sane. He only impressed upon him that he he was still sick and in need of medical assistance.[23]

The point that Kierkegaard thus expresses is this questionableness of objective truths. The statement which the patient from the asylum made was quite true and especially objectively true (that the earth is round). But is was of little consequence. Therefore we are to see that, while such objective statements can indeed by true, they do not lead us to eternal truth. In this respect they fall, because "Truth is Subjectivity".


180

For Kierkegaard, this subjective factor finds its culmination in the idea termed "passion". The highest of the passions of human subjectivity is faith.[24] This concept is a central one in the thought of this scholar. It opposed that portion of Western philosophy which reach its apex in Hegel, a tradition which stressed the importance of reason as the basis for knowledge.[25]

This understanding of faith (as the highest of the passions) as the basis of knowledge is an important factor when we are speaking of Kierkegaard's approach to God. Since subjectivity is the way to truth and faith is the highest expression of subjectivity, it follows that we can only come to know the truth about God by this subjective, inward faith. It is an inner process, a faith-experience, by which we come to know about Him.[26]

Since God can only be known by subjectivity such as is expressed in faith, it is therefore plain that we cannot gain such knowledge by any forms of objectivity, such as by reason. In fact, when we try to approach God by reason we find that He is inaccessible. It is plainly impossible to discover truth about God objectively.[27]

The same is true of the Christian faith as a whole because Christianity also opposed all objectivity. Kierkegaard even goes as far as to say that objective Christianity is paganistic.[28]


181

The culmination of these thoughts is in Kierkegaard's convictions that since God is a Subject, He can therefore only be known subjectively. Thus we cannot attempt any proofs for His existence, reason. It is little wonder that Kierkegaard does not try to demonstrate His existence.[29] 

This brings us to the crux of this presentation. It has been shown that Kierkegaard rejected verification and proof for the existence of God and for the Christian faith as a whole. Such as objective approach is clearly improper. Christian truth is achieved by subjectivity.

For there same reasons, Kierkegaard also rejected any attempts to base the truth of the Christian faith on historical knowledge.[30] In this he followed his predecessor, Gotthold E. Lessing (1729-1781), who postulated that "accidental truths of history can never become the proof of necessary truths of reason."[31] By this Lessing explains his conviction and belief that one cannot support Christian doctrines by referring to historical events that he has no historical ground on which to deny the resurrection of Jesus, this is no reason to believe


182

other doctrines of the Christian faith as a result. One may, indeed, affirm the other doctrinal beliefs of Christianity (as Lessing claims that he does), but this must be on another basis other than that of the historicity of certain events. To argue from such events would be to reason from accidental historical facts to the necessary truths of one's faith, and this is not allowable.[32]

Lessing adds that this division between historical facts and religious faith "is the ugly, broad ditch which I cannot get across, however often and however earnestly I have tried to make the leap."[33] Thus we perceive that the gap between these two categories is what comprises the barriers over which Lessing cannot find a way. There is no means he can discover which will allow one to proceed from an argument in the first category to a belief in the second category.

It is doubtful, however, if Lessing actually believed in a historical resurrection like he appears to affirm (as noted above). For instance, when writing in another essay about eighteenth century rationalist Hermann Reimarus' rejection of the resurrection, he admits that even if the objections which were raised were valid ones, Christianity depends upon faith and not upon historical events.[34] Even Kierkegaard realized that Lessing's affirmation about events such


183

as the resurrection were actually only concessions made by him to highlight the point he was making.[35]

In addition, Lessing relates that historical truths cannot be proven anyway. Thus, even if it is held that events have occurred, it cannot be proven that they did. In a similar way, just because the resurrection is believed to have actually occurred, it cannot be proven to have been historical, but only accepted by faith.[36] We can therefore better perceive how Lessing could seemingly accept an event even when it could not be demonstrated to have happened and when it could not be the basis for other beliefs.

Lessing's formulation, whereby history is divorced from faith, has exercised much influence since his time. For example, Immanuel Kant borrowed from him in making a similar distinction between the truths of God and historical fact. Separating these two categories is "a mighty chasm, the overleaping of which…leads at once to anthropomorphism."[37] Thus we find once again that religious truths of faith cannot be supported by history. And, as with Lessing, neither can events of history such as the resurrection be proven. In fact, this event cannot be demonstrated to have occurred literally because as such it is an offense to reason.[38]


184

Kierkegaard also followed Lessing in this belief that occurrences in history could not support religious truths of faith. Kierkegaard expressly states that "there can in all eternity be no direct transition from the historical to the eternal…"[39] This is the case both for the eyewitnesses to the facts and for those who are removed by generations. Whether the believer was a contemporary of Jesus or not, he is not able to base faith on reason or history.[40]

This stance by Kierkegaard is actually the key to this discussion. Since truth is subjective, then objective approaches such as the historicity of certain events cannot lead one to a decisive faith or to eternal happiness.[41] To be sure, this scholar believes that Jesus was a historical person in that he entered the time sequence of this world as man. It was also in history that Jesus lived, died and rose again.[42] But even though these events actually occurred, they comprise the supreme paradox of the Christian faith because the doctrine of the incarnation is seemingly inexplicable and difficult to grasp logically. Such events are contradictory because they assert that God has become man, contrary to all reason. Even though this incarnation really did take place in history, one cannot historically (or otherwise) demonstrate such events in Jesus' life


185

like the resurrection because it is impossible to demonstrate a contradiction (even one that really occurred). Historical proofs cannot make such events any less of a contradiction of paradox.[43]

Therefore, Kierkegaard postulated that these events cannot by the basis of faith, as mentioned above. But, in addition, they are to be believed even though it is not possible to demonstrate that they have occurred. Thus it is not only impossible to base one's faith of objective, historical events (since faith is subjectivity), but it is also impossible to prove these events. The various facets of Jesus' incarnation are an enigma to history and the objective discipline of history is too suspect and inexact to yield such proof.[44] For this reason, Kierkegaard discouraged arguing and debating about the truths of faith.[45]

The direct result of this emphasis upon theology is the very important concept termed the leap. Kierkegaard, inspired here by Lessing, makes much use of this idea.[46] For Kierkegaard, God cannot be determined to exist by "proofs", as mentioned earlier. Neither can His existence be demonstrated by pointing to events in history


186

such as the incarnation, as we have just seen. As long as we hold to such objective methods of verification, we will never understand God's existence. It is only when we let go of such proofs and accept God by faith that we will realize that God does indeed exist.[47] This act of abandoning all of our proofs and all of our attempts to reach God by reason, however brief a moment it may be, is termed a leap.[48] This leap takes place when we let go of all of these objective attempts to prove God by our reason and accept Him by faith.

So it is very clear that, for Kierkegaard, the resurrection of Jesus provides no basis for faith. Although this event is believed to be true, it cannot be demonstrated to be such. It must simply be accepted by faith apart from any historical logic. Once again we are required to reject this proof and perceive God without such a crutch. Thus, we are to take the leap to God's existence by faith, without any reliance upon historical fact. Lessing's ditch is bridged by faith, as one leaps from the facts of Jesus' life to faith in him apart from any verification.

So far, Kierkegaard's position concerning subjectivity has been investigated. To repeat briefly, this concept is viewed as being the proper way to finding the truth. A very clear statement to this effect is "Subjectivity is truth, subjectivity is reality."[49] This inward


187

quality of transformation reaches its apex in passion. In fact, passion itself is strictly a subjective factor which cannot be objective at all.[50]

This obviously leaves very little room for objectivity. Indeed, Christianity is opposed to all that is objective. If we rely on an objective faith we are said to be reverting to paganism.[51] There is actually even a limit place on reason, dictating its boundaries. This is because Kierkegaard believes that reason can only advance to a certain prove God. But even when reason is taken to its limit in relation to God, He is still no closer than before.[52]

We should also mention the personal quality of this faith. One believes in God even though this exercise of faith is not based upon any logical or other objective ground. Neither does this faith attempt to prove its own validity. Rather, the decision to act in faith involves the leap and one's subsequent embracing of subjective inwardness, which ultimately leads to a nonrational passion.[53]

It now remain for us to attempt to ascertain the accuracy of these views. We conclude above (in chapter four) that is theological investigations, reason is temporally first while faith is more important, especially as an end result. But there we have seen that


188

Kierkegaard gives no essential place to reason at all, while beginning and ending the theological process with faith. This leads to three major criticisms of Kierkegaard's approach, all of which are directed at the very heart of his polemic. One criticism concerns his exclusive use of faith and the other two revolve around his reluctant denial of any essential place being give to objective, reasonable approaches to Christianity.

The first major criticism concerns this scholar's internal consistency. As it questions the very point of whether Kierkegaard was successful in his own attempt to leave the objective approach to Christianity out of his view of faith.[54] It was concluded earlier (in chapter four) that reason, by definition,[55] was the grounds for all convictions and decisions. Any defense of a belief is also reason. Even the ability to think coherently is reason. This definition clearly thought (as opposed to subjective thought) is the very basis of our knowledge. In other words, Kierkegaard himself could not even provide such a polemic in defense of faith without relying on reason. This is because reason must be the basis


189

of his conviction that faith is primary. Reason must likewise have compelled his decision to act through such a faith-commitment.

Kierkegaard even makes use of logic and reason in his polemic in favor of the way of faith,[56] even though such an objective process also finds its basis in the rational. Thus there could not even be a defense of the primary of faith apart from some sort of rational process. Even though Kierkegaard does see some value in the objective, as noted above, he does not believe that it occupies a place of importance in reaching God. Neither does he accept reason as being temporally primary. The objection here is not that he gives no place at all to the objective, but that he does not realize that he is making use of such reasonable approaches in his own approach to God Therefore, even in his system, reason must be temporally first in order for Kierkegaard to assert the importance of faith.

This can be demonstrated more clearly when we remember how Kierkegaard postulated that truth is found in subjectivity and that objectivity was not the way to God. He could assert this, for instance, either by reasonable persuasion and rational argument or by intuitive conviction and knowledge. But now it is plain to see that reason, and not passion, is the origin of each. All processes of reasonable persuasion and rational argument obviously involve reason. But we have also seen that even the basis of such intuitive conviction or knowledge is reason. Should he try to demonstrate that this is not the case, this persuasion also becomes rational. One cannot show how subjectivity is central without utilizing reason.


190

Indeed, it would even be impossible for Kierkegaard to think in the sense that he was accustomed to at all, except by reason. He would be required to think through his position apart from the formulating of any convictions, without the formulating of any conclusions or without making any decisions in order to theorize apart from a rational process. It is therefore obvious that Kierkegaard did begin the process. It is therefore obvious that Kierkegaard did being the process. It is therefore obvious that Kierkegaard did begin the process with reason, as he was not able to simply start with faith.

It is therefore somewhat ironical that the very element which Kierkegaard sought to separate from faith (namely, objectivity) was the basis upon which faith was built. His very argument against this conclusion proved reason to be an essential element, since the very polemic was rational. Thus, however subjective or irrational the entire system may be, this subjectivity has been formulated upon a rational process, albeit a disguised one. Otherwise such a theoretical construction would not have been possible.

It is because of these factors that subjectivity, passion and faith cannot be held to be temporally fact. This position belongs to reason, even though faith is more important, especially in the end.

The second major criticism of Kierkegaard's system is that he does away with all logical grounds which might support his thesis. Even though it has been shown that Kierkegaard himself relies on an objective foundation in spite of his protests to the contrary, he still insists that there be no objective verification of faith. It is, or course, this scholar's express intention to do away with these grounds, but in so doing there is no objective criteria on which his claims may be based. In other words, Kierkegaard is in error by first denying a place to any objective basis for faith even when he


191

unknowingly utilizes such a reasonable basis himself (criticism number one above). But second, he continues to insist that faith cannot be verified at all. Therefore, even though it is his intention not to base faith on any objective foundation, it is because of this that one cannot ascertain if the subsequent message should be accepted or not. Since such faith is a personal, subjective experience, there is no reason someone else should likewise be compelled to accept it.

Or further, how would it be possible for one to know whether the Christian faith was the right religion? One could likewise urge faith in another system of belief. It no reasonable persuasion exists, how could Kierkegaard differentiate and choose between these options?

As stated earlier, since this faith which Kierkegaard proposes is do subjective, it is even hard to differentiate between it and human emotions such as elation, love or even heartburn. In other words, Kierkegaard's subjectiveness is not capable of answering these questions and those raised above because it cannot demonstrate its own validity or tell if its own foundations are solid. In the end there is no real way to ascertain is such a faith as been exercised is the proper way.

Even if Kierkegaard prefers a subjective faith, this does not answer the question of how he might be sure that this faith is valid even for himself, let alone for others. Just because this scholar is not interested in any objective demonstration of the Christian faith, it is nevertheless very important to be able to know if the faith-commitment which he is expounding is valid or not. After all,


192

faith is not simply a cerebral exercise devoid of consequences if it just happened to be false. Much is at risk for those who place high value (indeed, eternal value) in their faith it it is found to be illegitimate.

Kierkegaard speaks much of eternal truth, but it is hard to distinguish between real beliefs and false ones if there is no factual criteria. It is therefore essential to know if his system is probable. It becomes more obvious here that an objective, logical faith would thus be in a much better position to ascertain its trustworthiness than an irrational, subjective one.

For these reasons, for faith to be intelligible it must have some sort of objective groundwork. It the objective is rejected, as Kierkegaard does, then we must also abandon all hope of arriving at testable data about our beliefs. It is true that Kierkegaard was opposed to all such testing and demonstration, but without some criteria such as this, it would be almost impossible to know if such a faith was spurious ot not. Therefore we see that Kierkegaard's system of positing a faith which culminates in passion and inwardness in simply too subjective. There must be some reasonable basis upon which to build this faith.

There is also the problem that Kierkegaard claims that his method of faith is the only way that a Christian can find eternal happiness. But we submit that to abandon a rational basis for faith and to disregard intellectual demonstration can lead to eternal happiness only it one simply ignores any faith-related questions that might arise, such as these which have been raised here. One would have to wear earmuffs and blinders of irrationality in order


193

to forsake all needs and desires to rationalize just so that one might achieve a temporary and fleeting "eternal happiness" which lasts only until the next doubt arises. And the questions raised here would still remain unanswered--one would never know if one's faith-commitment was valid or even if it was warranted in the first place.

These first two criticisms alone are enough to provide an adequate critique of Kierkegaard's view of the Christian faith. But it is now possible to apply these two to his system with regards to his rejection of proofs and historical demonstrations as the basis of his way to God.

The third major criticism of Kierkegaard is that his rejection of any objective approach to the Christian faith, including historical verification, is no longer warranted in view of the preceding two criticisms. It has been shown that reason must remain temporally primary. Subjective factors such as faith and passion are unquestionably important, but these are to be based on reason. There must also be some objective grounds for faith. There are some definite implications in these conclusions.

It was stated earlier that the resurrection of Jesus was held by Kierkegaard as not being a valid basis upon which to rest the theological truths of faith. The reason for this was that the subjective was thought to be the true basis for belief. Such objective events were believed to be of a different category and are thus rejected.


194

But all of these convictions must change when it is held 1) that reason is temporally first and 2) that faith should be objectively verified, both of which were concluded above. For instance, since reason is held to be temporally primary (criticism number one here and chapter four above), one can no longer hold that the subjective stands alone and apart from this objective basis and neither can one negate the effectiveness of objective historical events as a result. In other words, with the former basis for religious truths dissolved (namely, subjective faith), the former reason for rejecting historical events must also disappear. This is because it can no longer be maintained that historical verification is opposed to an exclusively subjective faith, because it has been found that this faith is already based on an objective element, namely reason, And since this is the case, it must be realized that this reason can be historical reason, logic, or another means of reasonable verification. At any rate, one could not be opposed to such reasonable historical demonstrations when the objective objective element of reason is already inherent in the concept of faith, thereby requiring some such objective approach. In fact, the way is opened for faith to be verified by any reasonable approach (or even several at once).

It was also postulated above that faith must have some objective criteria on which to base its claims so that it can be verified (criticism number two here an chapter four above). The use of historical research provides and excellent means by which such verification can be effected. Therefore, we perceived once again that Kierkegaard's thesis subjectivity cannot stand. When this


195

scholar's emphasis on the exclusiveness of subjectivity fails, so does his polemic against proofs as are shown to be probable. It has been shown that faith must be confirmed as being the proper approach to God. Thus we can no longer rule out the confirmation which is provided by verification, such as that from past events which are found to be probable. Such objective demonstration is in fact demanded by the very nature of the two conclusions which we have reached here, as faith must be shown to be valid.

For these reasons, an exact inverse of Kierkegaard's relationships has therefore occurred. Whereas it was formerly not possible to accept historical events as pointing to eternal truths (according to this scholar), we now understand that this is no longer true. Historical verification (and other such objective demonstrations) now becomes a help rather than a hindrance, as it serves to validate and strengthen faith. In this way both the subjective faith and the objective demonstration are perceived to compliment each other.

These three criticisms against Kierkegaard must therefore be accepted as being valid, as they apply to all stages of his polemic. It was found that his starting point was not subjective faith but reason (criticism number one). Thus Kierkegaard is internally inconsistent from the outset by postulating faith as the initial starting point, but not realizing that he failed in this task himself. Since the main body of this work is predominantly subjective, this leads to another problem, namely that there is no way to ascertain if his system is valid or not (criticism number two). With no objective criteria with which to test there views, one cannot know if subjectivity is the best approach to God. From these first two


196

criticisms a third was deduced, that subjectivity is not solely the right approach to God, since we must start with reason and must utilize some objective criteria to verify faith. Thus it was found that one possible approach would be to use history to investigate the Christian faith (and the resurrection in particular) to se if it offers a solid basis for faith.

Suffice it to say that the way has thus been opened for the historical examination of events such as the resurrection. It this occurrence is found to be historical, it could be used as a more rational basis for Christian faith.

Although Kierkegaard's exclusively subjective basis for his system fails, his emphasis on a faith-commitment for salvation still remains valid This is especially so if historical (or other) evidence is found to verify such belief. This is because Kierkegaard is correct in establishing this as the central component of Christianity. The same conclusion was also reached in chapter component of Christianity. The same conclusion was also reached in chapter four above, where it was found that even though reason was temporally first, faith was the most important and essential element. Therefore we should still accept this conclusion as authoritative with an objective foundation. Kierkegaard's concept of the faith that leads to salvation and an authentic Christian life involves an individual's realizing that he is a sinner in need to repentance (a complete change of his life). This repentance is achieved by a complete surrender to God in faith, trusting the death of Jesus Christ on the cross to pay for all personal sins. The result is a total commitment of the individual to God for life of obedience, based upon the death of the Son of God. This total transformation of the person,


197

if genuine, leads to the joy of the Christian life. This is real faith.[58]

This definition of faith set forth Kierkegaard, as presented here, is quite a well-stated view. It also accurately portrays the New Testament teachings on this subject. We agree with this scholar that the summary just presented is the most important part of the reason-faith relationship and as such it is essential for the Christian belief in salvation. These teachings must therefore remain in our concept of Christianity. But we also believe that there are reasonable evidences which help to validate these teachings.


198

Chapter VIII.  Possibility Number Two: Other Similar Views

A. Karl Barth

We dealt above with some of the immense influence that Soren Kierkegaard's thought has had upon contemporary theology. His ideas were not very popular in his own day and did not become overly popular even in theological circles until the twentieth-century. At this time his views were revived by Karl Barth in particular and by those who followed him (usually referred to as Barthians or neo-orthodox theologians).[1] Especially influential was Kierkegaard's emphasis in the subjective approach to God which was discussed in the last chapter. Most of the neo-orthodox theologians agreed with him the God could not be approached by any rational means such as by proofs, historical demonstrations or other means of verification. Many also accepted the belief that faith entailed an irrational "leap".[2]

It is in the works of Barth which one can probably see the strongest influence of Kierkegaard on this last point. Barth also believed that God must be approach by faith and not by objective means. In fact, his methodology revolves around the analogy of faith. This concept was perhaps develop most consistently

 


199

in Barth's work Anselm: Fides Quarens Intellectum,[3] where this theologian concluded that Anselm's ontological argument for the existence of God was not a philosophical proof formulated to induce faith, for Anselm needed no such impetus in order to believe.[4] It is argued that Anselm admitted that the existence of God was known by faith and not by such demonstrations of His existence. This is true, Barth asserts, because it is impossible to learn of God by any kind of proof. We believe in Him not because He is known to exist by various procedures of verification, but because He has revealed Himself to us, especially by faith.[5]

For this reason, Barth rejects the analogy of being, which attempts to argue to the existence of God by various demonstrations. This is an abortive attempt to gain knowledge of God apart from faith. Since faith is not primary in such a system, it must be replaced by the analogy of faith.[6]

Thus, for Barth (as for Kierkegaard), faith is primary. The proper approach to God is the acceptance of faith without trying to verify this belief by proofs.[7]

  


200

When one endeavors to examine Barth's view of the resurrection of Jesus, it is important to keep in mind his methodology, Barth (again like Kierkegaard) therefore does not believe that it is possible either to demonstrate this event or to even or to use it as the reason why we should believe in God. This is because God can only be approached by faith and not be demonstrations such as those from historical events.

It is especially in the early period Barth's thought that the dialectical emphasis in neo-orthodox theology[8] played an important role. The approach taken to the resurrection is a good example of how this dialectic might be applied to theology. Barth was, for instance, able to say "Yes" to Jesus' resurrection being an actual event and "No" to its being a historical fact like other occurrences which can be historical verify. This sounds contradictory, but it is affirmed nonetheless:

In the Resurrection the new world of the Holy Spirit touches the old world of the flesh, but touches it as a tangent touches a circle, that is without touching it…The Resurrection is therefore an occurrence in history…But…The Resurrection is not an event in history at all.[9]

 


201

We have here an illustration which presents quite a seeming contradiction in terms. In the example chosen by the author, one must hold either that the tangent touches the circle or that it does not touch. But Barth affirms both. This example serves to illustrate a point in his theology, because in a similar manner he also affirms that the resurrection both is and is not an historical event. To the question of whether the resurrection is an actual event of historical, we therefore receive both a "Yes" and a "No" answer.

But how is this possible? Barth hold to the essential evil character of the world, which is tainted by sin. As such the world is opposed to God and His purpose. If Christ was really to enter the actual history of the world, then he would likewise participate in this evil.[10] For Barth "if the Resurrection be brought within the context of history, it must share in its obscurity and error and essential questionableness."[11]

The only possible conclusion is that the resurrection occurred on "the frontier of all visible human history."[12] It is a historical occurrence, but not in the normal sense of the word "history". In fact, it may be considered in some ways to be a nonhistorical occurrence.[13]

Barth continued a similar type of reasoning in other early works as well, 1920 he taught that the resurrection of Jesus was "not in


202

time. It is not one temporal thing among others."[14] An important distinction is made as follows:

The resurrection of Christ…is not a historical event…though it is the only real happening in is not a real happening of history (Italics and wording are Barth's).[15]

Again we see the distinction between an event occurring and its being a part of history. The resurrection can really have occurred and yet not happen like other events for this scholar. Barth even goes as far as to say that we should not ask whether it is historical or not, for this event is a good example of the nonhistorical and the impossible.[16] Even though it is an actual event, it cannot be proven or demonstrated to have occurred.[17]

In 1924 Barth published his work The Resurrection of the Dead.[18] Herein is contained essentially the same view of the resurrection as was present in his earlier works.[19] This even is again presented as occurring on history's frontier (or boundary) in such a manner that it can only be understood as God's revelation and not proven or demonstrated by history.[20]

An additional opinion is further given and clarified in this

 


203

work. Barth boldly asserts that alternate critical theories concerning the resurrection might even be true, for it makes no real difference if the tomb was closed or open that first resurrection morning. We accept Jesus' resurrection by faith and not because of any historical evidence. Thus this occurrence cannot be investigated or tested. It cannot be proven to have occurred.[21] Therefore, if there were news reporters present at the tomb of Christ on that first morning, they would not have been able to verify this event.

This last interpretation has been confirmed by American theologian Carl R.H. Henry, who questioned Barth on this very subject when he visited America some years ago. When Henry asked if our news correspondents could have reported the resurrection had they been there to investigate it, Barth responded by saying that it was a private event for the disciples alone. As the meeting broke up, one of the reporters remarked to Henry that the other writers had clearly understood Barth's answer. They knew that Barth was denying that they could have witnessed or investigated this event.[22]

Thus we perceive the view of the early Barth on the resurrection of Jesus. While this event is surely believed to have occurred, it is not an event of real history that can be investigated and demonstrated like other historical facts. Rather, it is not an event of history, but rather an occurrence of superhistory.[23]

 


204

Therefore the resurrection also happened in a different kind of history than has other events.[24]

Did Barth's position change substantially after his new emphasis on the analogy of faith in his work on Anselm?[25] According to Daniel Fuller, he did give more attention to the question of historicity, but he continued to reject the resurrection as an event which can be verified in any way.[26] One does readily notice this change, however, as it appears that more credence is given to the historical character of this occurrence. The objectivity of the resurrection is even stressed more, especially the fact that the disciples actually did see Jesus.[27] But Barth made it plain that he still did not hold that the facts of the historical Jesus should be stressed.[28]

In spite of this new emphasis, however, it is still obvious that Barth relegates the resurrection of Jesus to something other than the history in which other events happen. Scared event like the resurrection cannot be subjected to an already existing view of history. Rather, God's revelation through such occurrences demands a particular type

 


205

of history, a somewhat nonobjective, nondemonstrable variety. For Barth, there is such a definition of history which differs from the modern understanding of this word, and it is in this "metahistory" that Jesus is held to have risen from the dead. This event is judged to be historical by those who try to force the contemporary meaning of history upon it.[29]

In Barth's chief work, Church Dogmatic, we can plainly perceive the continuation of this stance. The resurrection is said to have occurred in a peculiar kind of history.[30] As "we pass from the story of the passion to the story of Easter we are led into a historical sphere of a different kind."[31] This is because the "death of Jesus can certainly be thought of as history in the modern sense, but not the resurrection…the history of the resurrection is not history in this sense…"[32]

Barth does give some vague indication as to the nature of the history in which he believes that the resurrection occurred. He relates several facts which serve in helping one to understand this peculiar mode of ascertaining certain incidents of the past. First, since this event is part of God's revelation (and this an act of God), it is different from other occurrences from the very outset.[33] But this is not the only reason we are given as to why the resurrection is perceived to occupy a different kind of history. We are told,

 


206

second, that this event is perhaps more properly viewed as being a "saga" or a "legend". As such it is termed "prehistory" because it cannot be understood historically in the modern sense of the word.[34] Here Barth identifies his concept more closely. There are also other differences between this prehistory and the modern concept of history. For instance, third (as we have remarked above), the resurrection not only cannot be proven to have occurred, but such a proof should not be attempted.[35] It is thus unlike other events which can be verified by historical research. Fourth, Barth boldly announces that it makes no difference if Jesus' tomb was open or closed on the first resurrection morning, for faith can follow from it nevertheless. In this way he asserts that the historical character of this event provides no foundation for faith.[36]

Barth's understanding of the resurrection therefore appears to be quite an elusive concept to grasp. Not only the initial revelatory character of this event, but even the event itself is prehistory or metahistory. It cannot be verified like other incidents and is construed in such a way that faith in it can remain even without various tend to point away from the historicity of this event and in spite of the insistence upon a different kind of history,[37] Barth still states that we cannot therefore say that Jesus did not rise, or that he did so only in a spiritual sense. We must understand that


207

this scholar still believed that Jesus rose from the dead in time and space in a objective way. Jesus had a body and he could be seen, heard and perceived to actually have risen from the dead.[38] While this conception of the resurrection appears quite contradictory,[39] it is another example of Barth's use of dialectic. He answers both "Yes" and "No" to the question of whether Jesus rose from the dead in actual human history.

We have seen that, whether we speak of the early or of the late Barth, we are dealing with a view of the resurrection that is essentially the same. Although a new stress is placed on the actual occurrence of this event in the later stages is placed on the actual occurrence of this event in the later stages of this scholar's work, the belief that the resurrection is not history in the same sense as other events, and therefore not provable, still persists. It is noteworthy that Kierkegaard also accepted this occurrence as an enigma for history, a paradox that cannot be understood or demonstrated by historical research. It can only be embraced by faith and not by the intellect.[40]

Barth's view of the resurrection has been discussed in depth, with the emphasis being laid primarily upon his understanding of this event as a type of prehistory which is not the old liberal view of myth, but neither is it one of complete historical objectivity.[41]

 


208

It has been our endeavor to be fair in this presentation, striving to deal adequately with both sides of this emphasis. It now remains for us to evaluate this approach.

Four major criticisms of Karl Barth's view of the resurrection will now be offered. The first, and one of the most comprehensive criticisms, involves the belief that the resurrection occupies a sort of parahistory which includes some aspects of objective history, while other facets of history are abandoned. Herein lies a mean problem of Barth's interpretation.

An event must either be some kind of a myth never literally occurred in actual human history, or it must have occurred in this same history. But Barth asserts that the resurrection is neither myth nor actual history in the modern sense. Rather, this event occurs in some sort of redemptive or religious history.[42] However, history simply knows nothing of such an "inbetween" ground, whether it is termed prehistory, saga, legend, or referred to as the boundary or frontier of history.[43] As Wand so perceptively points out:

History is concerned only with such events as happen within the space-time continuum. Events, real or imagined, which occur in a eternal or spiritual sphere are not the proper subject of history. The reason is that history has no tools by which it can deal with such events.[44]


209

In other words, history can only be concerned with events which occur in space and time in such a way that they can be investigated by the tools of historical research. Since there are no means whereby events which occur in a spiritual "inbetween" sphere can be so investigated, they are not actually within the scope of history. As Wand asserts, religious events which are perceived to have happened only in such an elusive realm cannot be properly regarded as history, whether these were real events or not. Historical facts must therefore be open to verification and research.

Admittedly, the resurrection (if it is found to have occurred) would have a different origin from other events because as such it would enter history as a direct act of God. The fact that Jesus' resurrection was not produced by any natural means, such as by historical causation, should not be belittled. Barth is correct in asserting that it is possible for an event to have its cause in Divine action and still be a part of history. Thus the resurrection would be unique in the sense that this event would have to have originated with God.

But there is an immense difference between saying that this occurrence would be unique because of its being a direct result of God's revelation and saying that as such it cannot be investigated. This is where Barth's polemic fails quite noticeably. The point here is that once this occurrence enters the realm of history (even though the actual entering is unique), it must be open to historical investigation. To forego such verification means that it does not become normal history at all. Thus, to remove such an event from investigation, as the scholar does, is not valid. One would have to also remove it from the scope of history as well in order to isolate it from such historical procedures.

 


210

Therefore, one cannot assert that certain events actually occurred and then add that we cannot speak historically about them or investigated them. Either the resurrection really happened in verifiable history or it did not happen in normal history at all. But let us not employ fancy theological verbiage to affirm its occurrence in a unverifiable, unobservable, contradictory realm of thought!

Pannenberg agrees in this criticism of Barth's view. He expressly states:

If we would forgo the concept of a historical event here, then it is no longer possible at all to affirm that the resurrection of Jesus or that the appearances of the resurrected Jesus really happened at a definite time in our world. There is no justification for affirming Jesus' resurrection as an event that really happened, if it is not to be affirmed as a historical event as such. Whether or not a particular event happened two thousand years ago is not made certain by faith but only by historical research, to the extent that certainty can be attainted at all about questions of this kind…The only method of achieving at least approximate certainty with regard to the events of a past time is historical research.[45]

As pointed out here, it is impossible for a theologian like Barth to say that an event occurred but not in the same objective history as other events occur. As Pannenberg adeptly points out, it is incorrect to claim to be speaking of Jesus' resurrection as a historical event if, as such, it can only be known by faith and not by historical research. It one asserts that something is not even able to be investigated, neither can one say that the event still happened at a certain time in this world. We this see that it is impossible for Barth to affirm that the resurrection really occurred while still having the understanding that this occurrence is not in objective, verifiable history. Such an event is not really  

 


211

history because no such concept of history exists. Therefore it is also impossible merely to claim that this event still happened just like other incidents in the past.

As a historian, Montgomery also objects to Barth's use of pre-history. The following illustration is introduced to demonstrate the folly of such a concept:

I wonder what you would say--what Barth would say--if I claimed that in my backyard there is a large green elephant eating a raspberry ice cream cone, but that there is no way by empirical investigation to determine that he is there. Nonetheless, I maintain, as a matter of fact, that it is there in every objective and factual sense. Now I have a feeling that you would either regard this as a claim that the elephant is there and is subject to empirical investigation, or contend that it isn't there by the very fact that there is no way of determining the fact. I wonder if this doesn't point up the problem. To claim objectivity, but to remove any possibility of determining it, is by definition to destroy objectivity.[46]

Montgomery's criticism is well justified. A historical event must either be open to investigation or not claim to be history at all for the very reason that it cannot be investigated. We destroy the concept of historical objectivity when we endeavor to rule that this objectivity itself cannot be tested. Any claim to a historical "middle ground" of prehistory removed from such processes of verification is about as accurate and acceptable as the claim concerning the existence of the green elephant.[47] Montgomery thus agrees with others that the idea of parahistory is foreign both to history itself and even to the Biblical records.[48]

Other theologians have also noted Barth's tendency to rely on the concept of prehistory and the subsequent weaknesses in his approach  

 


212

to the resurrection which have resulted. They realize both that historians recognize no such realm of history and that the very assertion that such a realm exists with both historical and non-historical characteristics is itself contradictory.[49]

The second major criticism of Barth is quite similar to one of the main objections of Kierkegaard and will therefore not be labored overly much here. Even though Barth claims that the resurrection literally occurred, we have seen how he denies any possibility of verifying this event. In fact, such a procedure should not even be attempted.[50] Thus, in spite of his emphatic assertions that the resurrection occurred, his view also falls prey to the criticism that there is no way for one to ascertain if the Christian faith is valid or not. We have already seen that faith cannot stand alone and be its own criteria and proof for belief. These subjective, personal qualities provide no reason why someone else should believe this particular system or accept Christianity over alternative views. Faith simply is not a panacea for all theological problems, because there is no reason to accept this faith if there are no ground upon which its claim may be based. In spite  

 


213

of Barth's defense of faith as the only way (as opposed to any historical research or other rational approach), it still remains that this faith cannot verify itself or demonstrate its own validity. This can only mean that one cannot know if the ground for belief are solid or not. There is no logical reason to accept such a faith.

In other words, to say that Jesus really rose from the dead but that this event can only be accepted by faith (without verification) is to leave one's entire faith open to question. Barth is of course not interested in verifying the grounds for Christianity. But without such objective criteria one can never know if one's faith is completely in vain or not.

Montgomery also realized the strength of such a criticism. Appropriating a fact by faith cannot make this belief factual. Simply by starting with faith we are not assured of arriving at a truthful, viable solution because the admonition to "have faith" cannot guarantee that one's beliefs are any more correct. Therefore, if faith does not have its starting point in objective, verifiable events, there is no way that one may ascertain if Christianity is the preferable faith-system in which to place one's trust.[51]

Therefore we perceive that which was stated earlier. Faith cannot create truth, not matter how instense is might be in the individual. Thus faith cannot make itself valid by its intensity or by the fervency with which it is exercised. Because of this, it is important for the individual to know if this faith is valid, and objective criteria are best suited for this purpose.

The last two criticisms of Barth are internal critiques. The

 


214

third major criticism concerns Barth's understanding of God's revelation in human events. It has been shown how this scholar contends that God reveals Himself in certain revelatory acts which occur in man's prehistory and not as an actual part of verifiable history.[52] But if revelation is not given objectively in historical facts which are open to historical Jesus' death cannot be revelatory because even Barth believes that the crucifixion is history in the modern sense of the word.[53] But Barth also holds that the crucifixion is part of God's revelation, since Jesus died a substitutionary death to pay for the sins of those who surrender their life to God in faith.[54] Here we find an internal inconsistency. If one holds that the death of Jesus is part of God's revelation to man (as Barth is correct in doing), then one must abandon the previously held idea that God never acts meaningfully is this kind of history. And if we reject this, it also means that the resurrection could likewise be objective, verifiable history and still be a revelatory event as well.[55]

The fourth major criticism of Barth's treatment of the resurrection is that this theologian holds that the New Testament itself does not make any attempt to demonstrate or prove that the resurrection did occur. He holds, rather, that the earliest Christians were only  

 


215

interested in accepting this event by faith. Thus Paul, for example, was not trying to present a proof of this occurrence by citing the witnesses in I Corinthians, chapter 15.[56]

It has already been noted above that this portion makes it quite plain that although Paul is speaking of the faith has its basis in objective, historical fact. The text clearly shows that Paul does intend to cite proof here, especially in verse six, where we are informed that most of the witnesses were still alive and could thus provide testimony concerning these events. This testimony would, in turn, provide historical eyewitness corroboration of Paul's claims.

Even Bultmann disagrees with Barth here, also noting that Paul does mean to use the list of the appearances of Jesus as proof for the resurrection.[] Bultmann notes that there were two current proofs for this event, both of which are found in I Cor. 15. There was the appeal to eyewitness testimony, as we have perceived here (especially 15:5-8) and the appeal to the fulfillment of Old Testament prophecy (15:3-4).[58] Bultmann's testimony is valuable at this point mainly because it is apparent that Barth is desiring to use the Scripture to reinforce his polemic,[59] whereas Bultmann actually  

 


216

objects to Paul's using such a proof in spite of believing that he does just this.[60] This desire of course does not in itself mean that Barth is necessarily wrong. But it does appear that Bultmann is more accurate in ascertaining Paul's obvious motives here.

Reginald Fuller is somewhat close to Barth in his view on this question. He holds that Paul's primary intention was to identify his preaching of the resurrection with that of the earliest eyewitnesses. But he also believes that Paul intended to relate the eyewitness accounts in order to prove that Jesus actually appeared to his followers. He likewise agrees in citing I Cor. 15:6 as the main pointer to the fact that Paul is establishing evidence to be used as proof for these appearances.[61]

But there are other portions of the New Testament which also establish the fact that other authors besides Paul endeavored both to prove the resurrection and to use this event as the basis for the establishing of other beliefs, contrary to Barth's view. It has been shown above how the gospels in particular sought to demonstrate the reality of Jesus' resurrection by stressing that he appeared to his disciples in bodily form. Although the new body had undergone some changes, it is reported that Jesus allowed his followers to examine and investigate this new body. We are even told that Jesus was touched an "held", thus demonstrating that he was alive. This emphasis is especially evidence in passages like Luke 24:36-43,[62] where ample evidence of this attempt to prove that Jesus had risen  

 


217

is readily available.[63] We are even told in Act 1:3 that Jesus "presented himself alive after his passion by many proofs…" (RSV). In fact, the Greek word used here for "proof" (tekmeriois) literally means a positive or certain proof.[64] Thus we see that it was the intention of several New Testament authors to prove that Jesus had risen.

In addition, it should be mentioned that the resurrection is also used in the New Testament as a proof for other Christian doctrines. For instance, Acts 17:30-31 shows that the earliest church believed that God verified Jesus' earthly teachings by raising him from the dead.[65] Acts 2:36 and Romans 1:4 are other example which point to Jesus' being accepted as the Lord, Messiah and the Son of God, based upon the resurrection.[66]

Thus we see that neither can Barth rely on Scripture for support of his thesis. The claim that the New Testament does not seek to prove or demonstrate that the resurrection actually occurred is simply not supported by the facts.

 


218

For the reasons we have given above, it becomes evident that Barth's thesis fails. These four criticisms of his view on the resurrection point out the key weaknesses to which this view is most vulnerable. They also reveal the inadequacies of this approach.[67]

3. Other Related Views

As Kierkegaard greatly influenced the views of Barth, so did Barth greatly influence the views of the many theologians who followed him. This is especially true on the question of the resurrection of Jesus. Many prominent neo-orthodox theologians in particular accepted these views.

For instance, Swiss theologian Emil Brunner apparently affirms belief in the resurrection of Jesus as having actually occurred.[68] But like Barth, he concludes that this occurrence is not part of the realm of normal, verifiable history. He relates that the resurrection is not an event which can be reported as is possible with other events.[69] In addition we also learn that this occurrence cannot be the basis for the Christian faith.[70] Brunner is careful to stress his view that the Christian's belief in Jesus' resurrection is no based upon any records contained in the New Testament,  


219

including the testimony concerning the appearances. We cannot resort to historical or other means of verification of this event. Faith come apart from any demonstrations or proofs that Jesus is alive. One simply accepts this by faith.[71]

Dietrich Bonhoeffer likewise relegates the resurrection to a realm other than normal history. He asserts:

The historicity of Jesus Christ thus comes under the two-fold aspect if history and faith. Both aspects are closely associated. The Jews of history humbled himself; the Jesus who cannot be grasped by history is the subject of faith in the resurrection.[72]

We are therefore to understand that Jesus' resurrection is not an event which can be understood historically. It cannot be verified or proven, but only accepted in faith. Bonhoeffer thus believed that the resurrection really occurred, but that it had to be received by faith, apart from any historical research.[73]

Reinhold Niebuhr rejected the resurrection of Jesus as an event in his early ears at Yale when he was still under the influence of liberal theology and it appears that he never changed his mind. The physical resurrection of Jesus had to be abandoned as an actual occurrence.[74] Nevertheless, he treated it as parahistory. Speaking of the death and resurrection narratives concerning Jesus, he concludes:

The story of this triumph over death is thus shrouded in a mystery which places it in a different order of history than the story of the crucifixion.[75]


220

Once again we find the belief that the resurrection did not happen in history in the same way that the crucifixion did. It therefore cannot be demonstrated to have occurred.

Barth's influence extended even further than the neo-orthodox theologians on the question of the resurrection. Gunther Bornkamm sounds surprisingly like Barth in his belief that the resurrection is not open to historical verification. It can neither be proven or observed like other events. Yet it is said to have occurred. As such it can be understood properly only by faith.[76]

Reginald Fuller speaks of the resurrection as the methahistorical and eschatological event. Something occurred as revelation from God. However, this event cannot be verified or otherwise proven because it is comprehended only be faith, having taken place on the boundary between this world's history and the methahistory of the eschatological age that is coming.[77]

Hans Grass also follows a line of thought somewhat similar to Barth's For Grass, the historical method provides no basis for investigating the resurrection. This occurrence cannot be approached by such methods of reason. But he differs from Barth in postulating that Jesus' appearances were spiritual and not physical at all.[78]

Jurgen Moltmann believes that the resurrection occurred, but that it cannot be historically demonstrated to have happened in the  

 


221

past. The theologian's object should not be to examine such past events, but to look to the future for the significance of them. Anyways, if we were to examine the resurrection by modern historical standards, it would be found to he historical impossible and meaningless.[79]

Moltmann's answer is to look for a new formulation of the concept of history. The resurrection is an eschatological event and as such it can be grasped historically at all only when it is viewed as to its future significance.[80] Thus, while Moltmann seemingly rejects the view of prehistory,[81] he still holds that the resurrection should be relegated to a different, eschatologically-oriented concept of history. He is quite specific in his belief that the resurrection was not observable and that this event cannot be verified at present.[82] Thus he also takes flight to a different sort of history in which past events such as the resurrection cannot be historically proven to have occurred apart from future vindication.[83]

We have already presented a critique of these theological attitudes while discussing Karl Barth's position. Almost the exact same criticisms also apply to the others (at least to the neo-orthodox  

 


222

theologians which we have discussed). Perhaps the man criticism involves placing the resurrection in prehistory or parahistory. While details as to what realm this is may differ somewhat (we have studied Barth's view in dept above), sociologist of religion Peter L. Berger's criticisms still apply. First, this category has no meaning for a scholar who desires to empirically investigate the data. One who supports such a view of parahistory has already chosen to leave the empirical realm of investigation. This concept is meaningless in this context. Second, this method is resigned to the few who feel that they have already attained the proper outlook with regard to theology.[84]

With a few variations, the following summary of criticisms applies at least to Barth and scholars like Brunner and Bonhoeffer. They are also more-or-less applicable to the others covered here, at least in part. First, history knows of no such concept as prehistory. It is not possible to measure or investigate such a realm. In addition, the inclusion of both historical and nonhistorical characteristics renders such a category contradictory. Real history can be investigated and examined to determine if it is valid or not. One cannot make the claim that an event is real history and then not subject it to investigation. Even if a metahistorical even were possible, it must either be verifiable or not claim to be real

 


223

history at all. Therefore this concept must be rejected. Second, the stress on one's affirming the resurrection by faith and the refusal to demonstrate this event by any other method means that this view is not objective enough to provide sufficient reason for one to know if the Christian faith is valid. An intense belief cannot make this faith any more valid. With no such methods of investigation we cannot know if such faith is simply in vain.

Third, neo-orthodox theology contends that God's revelation does not primarily occur in actual history in the modern sense of the word.[85] Yet Barth, for instance, bases the revelation in the death of Christ on what he admits to be an actual historical fact, while refusing to do this in the case of the resurrection. He is therefore internally inconsistent in holding that the resurrection cannot likewise be based on actual historical fact. Fourth, at least Barth contends that the New Testament does not attempt to prove the resurrection. The others at least agree that his even cannot be demonstrated. But Barth's contention is not based on the available evidence. Contrary assertions in the New Testament invalidate there claims and thus cannot be used to support this thesis.

For these reasons, it is our conclusion here that such an approach to the resurrection is untenable. One cannot remove this event and, subsequently, the entire Christian faith, from the realm  


224

of investigation. There are simply too many difficulties for one to hold to such a position. But as Kierkegaard's view, so Barth's emphasis on faith and its importance can remain. We have mentioned above how that Barth conceived of the death of Christ as being a substitutionary death to pay for the sins of those who surrender their life to God in faith.[86] This view of faith must be retained. As it was concluded earlier in chapter four, faith must remain the most important element in a theological system. This is even shown to be more true if there is an objective basis on which to rest this faith.

 


225

Chapter IX. Possibility Number Three: That the Resurrection Did Occur and That It Can Be Demonstrated

A. Wolfhart Pannenberg: An Introduction

The third major possibility to be dealt with in this work is that Jesus' resurrection really id occur and that this occurrence can be demonstrated.[1] We will begin by examining the position of a very important scholar in contemporary theology today who holds this view. This theologian, Wolfhart Pannenberg (born 1928), is without much doubt the best-known representative of this viewpoint today.

Pannenberg has received much acclaim in recent years because of his defense of the historicity of the resurrection. In fact, he has been viewed by many as "the theologian of the resurrection".[2] It is this event which forms the basis for his polemic and which sets the stage for his theological system.[3] Now it is by no means unique either to defend the historicity of the resurrection or to use it as the basis for one's theological system.[4] But Pannenberg is probably  

 


226

the theologian who is best known for these tendencies. Therefore he becomes the logical choice as the primary scholar to be dealt with here.

Wolfhart Pannenberg is often connected with a new school of theology in Germany which is usually referred to as the "theology of hope." This generally optimistic understanding of theology was welcomed in the United States in the late 1960's by some of the leading newspapers and magazines. These publications seemed to be more than willing to report the demise of the pessimistic and short-lived reign of the "death of God theology" and greet instead its more hopeful and reassuring "successor".[5]

The motif of hope in many ways presented quite a novel approach to theology, being one of the first theological schools of thought that was not a development of the earlier dialectic theology of Karl Barth and those who followed him. Among others, those usually connected with the theology of hope are German theologians Pannenberg, Jurgen Moltmann, Johann Metz and sometimes Karl Rahner.[6] However, it is actually difficult to be overly suggestive when speaking of those who favor this approach, and it is really only possible to speak rather generally of any group of "hope theologians."[7]

 


227

While Pannenberg was earning his doctorate at the University of Heidelberg in the early 1950's, a group of graduate students began meeting and exchanging ideas on the nature of Divine revelation. Apparently in opposition to Pannenberg's own wishes, this group began to be referred to as the "Pannenberg circle". The combined work of four of the "members"--Pannenberg, Rolf Rendtorff, Trutz Rendtorff and Ulrich Wilkens--produced the volume Offenbarung als Geshichte[8] in 1961. It represented years of study and discussion together.[9]

Although this work was not the first one of Pannenberg's to be translated into English, it was still significant in that it helped to bring this German scholar to the attention of other theologians. Perhaps Pannenberg's most significant work to date, Jesus--God and Man, was translated into English in 1968. It was his first major work to appear in an English translation. This Christology has been recognized by some theologians as one of the most significant to appear in many years.[10]

It soon became evident that Pannenberg's thesis was opposed to many aspects of Barth's and Bultmann's theology. For instance, Pannenberg was opposed to the subjectivism exercised by both of these theologians.[11] He also objected to Barth's concept of revelation,   

 


228

especially with regard to Barth's view that certain events such as the resurrection happened in a nondemonstrable, nonverifiable type of history. Pannenberg believed that such events both can and should be historically investigated, in opposition to Barth.[12] This, of course, also means that Pannenberg likewise objected to Bultmann's even more complete divorce history from faith.[13]

With this introductory background, it is now advantageous to turn to Pannenberg's argument concerning the resurrection of Jesus. Both a presentation of these view and a critique of them will be given. It should be remarked that the following is not a presentation or discussion of the entire theology of hope, but only of Pannenberg's views on these subjects.

B. Wolfhart Pannenberg's Argument and a Critique

To put Pannenberg in proper perspective, it should be mentioned that the theology of hope stresses eschatological theology and the coming Kingdom of God in particular. The coming of the Kingdom has political an ethical repercussions, as will as theological ones. Also stressed is the death and resurrection of Jesus as historical events which set the stage for this eschatology, as will be perceived below.[14]

 


229

One of Pannenberg's chief aims is to restore to contemporary theology the concept of a functionally imminent Kingdom of God.[15] Most of contemporary theology is perceived to have failed in its approach to the Kingdom in that the eschatological centrality of this concept has been lost. But for Pannenberg, the teaching about the Kingdom must be the central message in Christian theology.[16]

The future Kingdom of God holds a special interest for Pannenberg with regard to God's existence. God is identified with the coming Kingdom in such a way that, in certain sense, God does not exist as yet. It is only with the arrival of the future Kingdom that the existence of God is shown to be a definite reality.[17]

But this by no means signifies that God is now present in this age or that He was not present in the past. The idea that God's existence is fully revealed in the future therefore does not disqualify Him from present existence. From His future existence God dominates both the past and the present.[18]

At first this concept of the existence of God appears contradictory. But actually the "secret" is in understanding Pannenberg's ideas about the retroactive power of history and the ability of the future to reach backwards into the past. God exists at present (and in antiquity) in the sense that His future is reaching back into the past. He thus   

 


230

exists at present as the partial arrival of the future.[19]

According to Pannenberg's concept of theology, it is God who will usher the Kingdom into human society. God thus works in the future as well as in the present. This Kingdom is not synonymous with the church, and neither will it arrive by man's power. He is quite emphatic that it will become part of history by the future actions of God Himself, even though there are present ramifications of the Kingdom as well.[20]

But it is not only the existence of God which reaches into the present from the future. In fact, all occurrences eventuate from the future.[21] As Neuhaus explains, we therefore cannot only refer to the future of an event simply as something which will happen, but rather as something which reaches back into the present and which is now in existence. Although one can perceive the final state of something only in the future, the affects are present.[22]

For instance, the authority of God was retroactively present in the teachings of Jesus.[23] This is shown to be the case especially be Jesus' resurrection from the dead.[24] In a similar way the Kingdom has also reached back into this present time, although it has not arrived in its fullness.[25] It is through such a stress on the

 


231

fundamental importance and priority given to the future that Pannenberg can speak of the end time having participated in the life of Jesus.[26]

In Revelation as History Pannenberg wrote two key essays. In one, entitled "Dogmatic Thesis on the Doctrine of Revelation", he postulated seven theses which are crucial to the understanding of his thought. This essay set forth much of the foundation of Pannenberg's theological system and expands on the points raised above. These theses are especially instrumental in pointing out the extremely important place that the resurrection of Jesus plays. Seeing this event in the context of Pannenberg's theological enterprise will allow for a much better understanding of this scholar and will also make the ensuing critique more accurate and meaningful. For these reasons the seven theses are presented below, with a short discussion of each included. Related key thoughts of Pannenberg's on Christology and eschatology will also be presented in the appropriate places.

Pannenberg's first thesis is that God's Self-Revelation is not direct, but indirect effected by God's historical acts.[27] After a brief survey of some of the prominent views of Divine revelation, Pannenberg asserts that God did not reveal Himself to man by the announcement of His name to the Israelites, or by the inspiration of the Scriptures, or by the giving of the law on Mount Sinai or by any other direct means.[28] To the contrary, God revealed Himself indirectly through historical acts in both the Old Testament. He made  

 


232

Himself known by means of a revelation which is grounded in history.[29] The chief purpose of Pannenberg's essay is to explore this indirect revelation and to ascertain its value as God's chosen method of revealing Himself.[30]

An interesting aspect of this belief in the indirect self-manifestation of God in human history is that Pannenberg conceives of this revelation as permeating all of human history. God therefore does not simply reveal Himself in some small segments of history exclusive of other areas. Rather, the indirect revelation of God occurs in all of man's history. For this reason, Pannenberg relates that there can be no such thing as "Supernatural events" or miracles". Since God works in history as a whole, this means that we cannot speak of Supernatural history versus natural history. No such dichotomy exists. We are thus to perceive that God reveals Himself in all of human history, and since He works in all of history we are not to think of separate miracles or Supernatural events apart from the whole of historical revelation.[31] Pannenberg realizes that this is not a new conception of revelation, as similar views were expressed in German idealism.[32]

  


233

The key to thesis one is thus that God does not reveal Himself directly. Any understanding of the concept of revelation that asserts otherwise is therefore not correct. God only allows Himself to be known indirectly, and that is through His acts in the whole of human history.

Pannenberg's second thesis is that God's revelation is not known totally at the beginning, but rather at the conclusion of revelatory history.[33] Since God only reveals Himself indirectly, Pannenberg believes that it is therefore correct to link this revelation with the end of history.[34] Thus the early events in the history of Israel whereby they learned of Yahweh were not the final or the most important of God's acts. The most important revelation will occur only at the end of history.[35]

Some of the logic of this position has been presented above. It has been stated that Pannenberg conceived of the end of history in such a way that the future can have a retroactive affect upon both the past and the present. As such, all occurrences eventuate from the future. According to this understanding, God can be more-or-less identified with the coming Kingdom and still have existed so as to have dominated the past and the present. In a similar way, the resurrection is the sign that God's activity was also retroactively present in the left of Jesus.[36]

 


234

Pannenberg thus accepts the priority of the future. Even at present the future is more important. This is seen, for instance, by this scholar's belief that all events reach into the past and the present from the future.[37] Since these postulates are believed to be valid, one can therefore perceived how Pannenberg further held that the final truth and result of an event is determined by the future of that event and not only by its present appearances.[38]

The natural outworking of this concept is that in the resurrection of Jesus the future already participated in the past. Through this event the God of the coming Kingdom retroactively acted in the life of Jesus. It is an event such as this that illustrates the second thesis concerning how God's indirect revelation will be accomplished primarily at the end of revelatory history rather than at the beginning.[39] Another pointer to this second thesis is Pannenberg's belief that it is only with the arrival of the end of history that God will prove Himself to be definite reality. Again revelation is perceived to be complete at the end of revelatory history.[40]

The third thesis which is presented by Pannenberg is that God's historical revelation is not restricted to special or private situations,   

 


235

but is open for all men to see. In this sense, revelation is universal.[41] Thus one is not to understand revelation as something secret or mysterious. It is not an entity which is known only to those who have been initiated into the life of faith. In face, an individual need not even have faith first in order to see God's revelation. This is because one's faith is inspired be seeing the revelatory events. In other words, faith need not precede the perception of revelatory events, but arises after the recognition of them.[42]

As to the nature of the revelatory events in question, Pannenberg asserts that God has acted throughout the history of Israel all the way to Jesus' resurrection. These events communicate meaning to those who perceive and appropriate them. They are comprehended by reason and are open to the examination of all.[43]

By postulating that God's revelation is open for all to see and examine, Pannenberg is further giving explanation to this belief that Christianity is a rational faith. One is not required to make a leap of faith so that one might be able to believe in God. Such irrationality has no place in the Christian faith. One believes because the facts are found to be reliable and trustworthy.[44]

Pannenberg realizes that there is a subjective factor involved when one speaks of a historical verification of one's faith and that one therefore cannot reach absolute results when studying history. Yet history is the proper method to use in examining the claims of   

 


236

Christian revelation, as it is capable of leading one to highly probable conclusions.[45] Therefore, historical examination of events such as the resurrection is needed to ascertain whether the reports are true or not.[46] One thing which Pannenberg insists upon in this research is that the investigator must be open to the results of the research and not have made up his mind in advance as to what did or did not happen.[47]

Pannenberg's fourth thesis is that God's universal revelation of His deity is not yet known in Israel's history. Rather, it was first revealed in Jesus' fate in that the end of history is already anticipated in this event.[48] In the ancient history of the Jews, Pannenberg is convicted that God did not show Himself to be the God of all mankind. Rather, he was seen as the God of Israel.[49] but in the New Testament, God was shown to be the God of all mankind be His act of raising Jesus from the dead. Through this act all men can look to the God of Israel as the only true God. Through the life and teachings of Jesus, the offer of the Kingdom is extended to all people.[50]

It is obvious that the resurrection holds a place of great importance in Pannenberg's theological enterprise. Indeed, this scholar's works reflect the Pauline conviction that if Christ had   

 


237

not risen, all faith would be in vain.[51] It is therefore important for one know if this occurrence is a historical fact which can be demonstrated. Pannenberg advocates examining the sources to see if any alternate explanations could account for the rise of the resurrection faith.[52] He entertain such hypotheses as the subjective vision theory,[53] the legend or myth theory,[54] and Barth's view of the resurrection happening in prehistory.[55] After a careful look at such theories, Pannenberg concludes that the resurrection of Jesus from the dead is the only adequate explanation for the subsequent faith of the disciples. Those who seek to deny the reality of this event must be prepared to provide a more adequate explanation. Pannenberg believes that the inevitable conclusion is that the resurrection can be verified as having occurred in human history.[56]


238

The fifth thesis which Pannenberg presents is that the deity of God is not revealed in the Christ event as an independent or isolated fact, but only as the event is part of Israel's history.[57] The Christ event cannot be separated from Israel's history because the God of Christ is also the God of the Old Testament. Jesus' mission and fate must therefore be understood from within the framework and context of Israel's history.[58] As such the resurrection remains the revelation of God whereby the end times have retroactively taken part in Jesus' fate.[59]

Pannenberg's sixth thesis is that the universality of God's eschatological participation in Jesus' fate found its actual expression in the Gentile Christian church's non-Jewish understanding of revelation.[60] The coming of the gospel to the Gentiles was a natural and necessary consequences of the eschatological significance of Christ. Bu Pannenberg assert that there were differences between the Gentile and the Jewish conceptions of revelation. The influence of Gnosticism is said to have brought some non-Jewish elements into the Gentile understanding of God's revelation. For instance, Gnosticism taught that revelation was direct and that it was imparted by means of secret initiation and knowledge, thus meaning that it was not available to the scrutiny of all men.[61] It has already been pointed out how Pannenberg conceived of Jewish   

 


239

revelation as being both indirect (by means of God's historical acts) and open for all to perceive.

Pannenberg believes that even though these important differences existed between the Jewish and Gentile ideas of revelation, the Christian conception of God's acting in Jesus in a final and universal manner still made its way extensively into the Gentile-gnostic concept of revelation, for these portions still served to make God understandable to both Gentiles and to Jews. In other words even though Pannenberg believes that Gnosticism influenced portions of the New Testament teaching on the revelation of God in a way opposed to the Jewish concept, it must be realize that this still helped in causing the Gentiles to know that God was the God of the Gentiles as well as of the Jews. God's actions in Jesus' fate therefore were shown to be universal in scope in that the Gentiles responded to this revelation and accepted it as having been extended to them as well.[62]

The seventh thesis presented by Pannenberg asserts that the imparting of God's word is related to revelation by its foretelling, forthtelling and report.[63] Even though Pannenberg understands that any reference to the Biblical word of God as the direct revelation of God is influenced by gnosticism,[64] there is still a threefold relationship between these two concepts. First, the indirect revelation through historical acts confirms the promises which God   


240

had given beforehand. Here the word sets the stage for the revelatory actions by foretelling the promises of God which are then fulfilled in the revelatory future. Second, the words of God confirm His acts in history in the sense that they follow the revelation as forthtelling. In this sense, the actions of God establish the words that follow, such as with the Law or other commandments which were given to the people after they had seen God act. Third, emerging in the New Testament one finds that the kerygma acts as a report of what historical acts God has already performed. There can be no universal significance of God's relationship between word and revelation points to a spoken proclamation regarding the preceding revelation.[65]

None of these relationships between revelation and word give and revelatory nature to the word. The word of God, either spoken or written, is therefore conceived by Pannenberg as supplementing the actual revelation without being the revelation itself. The word may precede the indirect revelation in the form of a promise as to what God will do in the future (foretelling), or the word may follow the revelation, having been established by the acts of God (foretelling). Yet again, the word may be a proclamation of the revelation (report). Thus the word may serve to explicate or proclaim revelation, or else the word may itself be expanded, verified or established by the revelation. At any rate, the word is therefore related to the revelation without being the revelation itself.[66]

 


241

From Pannenberg's presentation of these seven theses one can perceive how the past revelatory acts of God (both in Israel's history and in the life of Jesus) and the future revelation of God are believed to be intricately interwoven. This scholar has indeed developed a theological system which seeks to explain the Biblical concept of God's indirect Self-revelation through His actions in history. However, Pannenberg fails noticeably in at least four key areas of his work, which will be investigated here.

The first major criticism of Pannenberg concerns his concept of God. This criticism is directed against the aforementioned understanding of God as reaching from a future existence into the past. Pannenberg believes that this view of God is confirmed by the Scripture and especially by the preaching of Jesus. In the view of this scholar, Jesus conceived of God's claim to this world exclusively in futuristic terms. God is said to be in a process of coming to exist and so in a certain sense does not exist at present.[67]

On order to make the assertion that the New Testament also expounds this futuristic view of the existence of God , it appears that Pannenberg has to ride roughshod over the Scriptural evidence to the contrary. It is agreed that the main emphasis in Jesus' teaching is on the coming Kingdom of God and the resulting present faith-obedience to God.[68] But this is far from sufficient proof to require God's primary existence as issuing into the present from the future. In fact Jesus seems to indicate the origin of God's   

 


242

existence as being different than Pannenberg asserts.[69]

For instance, when Jesus refers to the eschatological judgment of the future, he likens it to the past judgment that God meted out both in the days of Lot and in the days of Noah (Luke 17:26-30, 32; cf. Matt. 24:37-39). When on another occasion Jesus was asked for a sign, he did not point forward to any events in the future, but backwards to the prophet Jonah, who was to be a sign of his resurrection form the dead (Matt. 22:39; c. Matt. 16:4, Luke 11:29- 30). Also, when questioned about divorce Jesus informed the questioner that God acted out of the pasted in making provision for marriage. Jesus refers his listeners to the mighty act of the creation of God for their answer concerning the seriousness of divorce (Mk. 10:6-8; Matt. 19:4-6).

Therefore it is obvious that Pannenberg is not correct in his statement that Jesus spoke exclusively of God in terms of His future rule.[70] To the contrary, several portions of the gospels indicate rather that Jesus also looked into the past for the unveiling of God's power. Jesus thus does not speak of God exclusively in futuristic terms, unless one has already assumed in advance that God works from the future into the past.

Now Pannenberg can admittedly explain there verses in which Jesus refers to God's power as also being demonstrated in the past. There were not supposed to be verses which be would no explain. The simply show that Jesus looked to the past as well as to the future in order to reveal the workings of God. There are admittedly many 

 


243

verses which do indeed refer to future acts of God, but there are also ones dealing with His past actions. However, the significant point here is that Pannenberg can interpret that past actions of God according to his system only by utilizing the prior presupposition that God is already in the future, working into the remote past. His view that God reveals Himself only from the future is an unsupported assertion, and it is shown to be so simply by the fact that it must be assumed to be true before it can be accepted, as will be shown in the third criticism of Pannenberg below. He cannot point to these verses as ones which support his ideas, for they do not. He can only interpret them according to already existing assumptions.

But from whence does the actual idea that God exists primarily in the future arise? One might stress verses on the other end of the spectrum and build a case around the thesis that God exists primarily in the past and is revealed particularly through His creation. From this past existence He would then reveal Himself in the present and in the future. Verses pertaining to the future Kingdom of God would then be applied to the final and complete revelation of God. As clever as such systems can be made to sound, they appear to be based more upon philosophical speculation than upon theological revelation.

The point here is therefore not that Pannenberg cannot deal with these preceding verses, but rather that he must assume the primary importance of the future in order to do so. Both his thesis and the contrived one that perceives God to have acted mainly from the past through the creation-event thus have the same problem. There is a lack of proof. Both views have inadequate reasoning justify such a view of revelation. For instance, there is no support in the New    

 


244

Testament accounts of Jesus' teachings to justify the position that God does not yet exist, in whatever sense this may be taken. Neither does Jesus teach that God is in s process of coming into existence.[71] It is plain that in other similar ways as well, Pannenberg's overall conception of God appears to be based more upon philosophical speculation than upon revelation. There is a decided lack of evidence for his view.

The second major criticism of Pannenberg concerns his hypothesis that God reveals Himself indirectly only through His actions in human history. For this scholar, God did not reveal Himself through any direct means, such as by the inspiration of the Scriptures, but only indirectly through the events of human history.[72]

Many theologians are of the persuasion that God acts in history and that this is one means of revelation.[73] But fewer are convinced that this is the only means of God's revelation. Certainly another shortcoming of Pannenberg's is in not recognizing the self-witness of the Scriptures as being another revelation of God, especially in portions which could not have been influenced by gnosticism.[74]


245

Pannenberg contends that the New Testament witness to the direct revelation of God in the Scriptures reflects the early influence of gnosticism, as already shown above. This direct Spiritual revelation is held to be contrary to the Jewish understanding of God's indirect revelation is history. To be sure, he does allow a close connection between the written words and this revelation.[75] but it appears that Pannenberg ignores the Old Testament witness to God's revelation in Scripture and through the prophets. This attestation would of course be removed from the influence of first century gnosticism.

A very clear reference to God's speaking through the Old Testament prophets is found in Number 12:6, 8. Here we are specifically told that God used this means to make Himself known to the Jewish nation. This is both an early and quite clear reference to the Jewish belief that God did reveal Himself to the Jews through the prophets. Statements such as this one in Number could be multiplied considerably.[76] In fact, hundreds of times in the Old Testament the phrase "thus said the Lord" serves to introduce a revelation of God for the people.[77]

The Jews were even responsible for distinguishing between the prophet who spoke the words of the Lord and one who did not. The sign that the prophet was relaying a revelation from God was that the prophecy would occur in history. Thus, the true prophet was one who   

 


246

correctly received revelation directly from the Lord and then proclaimed it to the people with his word being confirmed by history (see Deuteronomy 18:20-22). The Old Testament therefore not only teaches that God's indirect revelation is manifested in history, in this instance by the fulfillment of prophecy, but also that God's direct revelation is given to the prophets, through whom God makes Himself known.[78]

However, the Old Testament witnesses report that God not only revealed Himself throught the preaching of the prophets, but also through the written Scriptures. There is even a relationship between re revelation given to the prophets to speak and the recording of this revelation in written words, as the prophets were quite often required to record the words of their prophecies.[79] For instance, Moses[80] was commanded not only to speak the words of God, but also to write the words which has been revealed to him.[] This means that God's revelation also comes through the written words of the Scriptures.[82]

 


247

Other prophets besides Moses are also commanded to write the revelation which was communicated to them by God. This is found to be the case with Isaiah (Is. 8:1; 30:8), Jeremiah (Jer. 36:2) and Habakkuk (Hab. 2:2). It is recorded that David also both spoke and wrote God's revelations to him.[83]

It is now plain from this preceding brief survey that Pannenberg's limitation of revelation to God's acts in human history is only presenting a part of the whole. In spite of this scholar's claim that his view faithfully represents that of ancient Judaism, it has been shown here that this is not the case.[84] The Jewish concept of revelation also includes at least the revelation given to prophets to speak the word of God and the revelation which is written in the form of Scriptures. It is true that the Jews believed that God revealed Himself indirectly through historical acts. But it is also true that the Jews believed that God revealed Himself directly through the prophets and through the written word in the Scriptures. A proper view of Jewish revelation must include all of these factors and not just the first, as Pannenberg does.


248

It is Pannenberg's opinion that only gnosticism teaches such direct revelation,[85] yet it has been shown that even in the earlier Old Testament writings this view is found. To claim the influence of gnosticism here is therefore clearly impossible. Rolf Rendtorff also asserts that God never revealed Himself in the prophetic word,[86] yet it has also been shown that several Old Testament passages teach the contrary view. Especially noteworthy is Num. 12:6:

If there is a prophet among you, I the LORD make myself known to him in a vision, I speak with him in a dream (Num. 12:6, RSV, italics added).

As if to say that this Self-revelation of God was not direct enough in some instances, Num. 12:8 adds concerning Moses that:

With him I speak mouth to mouth, clearly, and not in dark speech; and he beholds the form of the Lord (Num. 12:8, RSV).

There can be no question about the intention of these two verses. God made Himself known to the prophets, but He revealed Himself even more directly to Moses. The Lord's "making Himself known" must necessarily involved Self-revelation. Other verses pointed out above also assert these beliefs. By making known His present admonitions for holy living by revealing the future by his prophets, it was believed that God was revealing Himself directly to the people. This was done by God's chosen messengers through both the spoken and the written word.[87]

 


249

Pannenberg's view of revelation therefore fails in its attempt to present the only revelation of God as being indirect by means of God's acts in human history. This is just a part of the Jewish concept, which also includes direct revelation through the oral proclamation and through the written word.

The third major criticism of Pannenberg is one which recurs throughout much of his work and is especially obvious in his presentation of his seven theses. Pannenberg's view of revelation in its relation to the future contains several inadequately supported statements. His theological system does include many intriguing and alluring points, some of which are certainly valid.[88] But the overall framework for this system, especially concerning God's revelation of Himself from the future, sometimes appears to be composed of assumptions which lack proper evidence. This has been perceived to some extent in the first objection above. Thus McDermott notes here that Pannenberg is sometimes guilty of inserting reality into a future which has obviously not yet arrived, and that he has done so without the proper clarification and evidence.[89]

Instances of this lack of evidence are readily available, and clearly affect the framework of Pannenberg's theological system. Pannenberg admits that his work rests upon two presuppositions, thee being the reality of the future's power and the single future which exists for every event.[90] These two presupposition are quite apparent   

 


250

in his seven theses, but strangely without supportive evidence in many cases.

For instance, the second thesis calls for a relationship between revelation and the end of all history. This relationship is said to be the result of the indirect nature of this aforementioned revelation. In fact, the connection of revelation with history's end is said to be the direct result of the indirectness of revelation.[91] But even if one were to grant the indirect nature of God's revelation in history,[92] how does this cause revelation to be known primarily at the end of history? Pannenberg never succeeds in demonstrating how indirect revelation automatically means that this revelation must be connected with the end of history. God could quite conceivably be acting indirect in history from out of the present. In other words, Pannenberg has not shown why futurity must follow from indirect revelation. One must assume that his view of God is the definitive one to even begin to arrive at this conclusion, and we have already seen that this view is quite arbitrary and problematical as well.

Another example of Pannenberg's arbitrary theology occurs in the fourth thesis, where Jesus' fate is also connected with the end of history. Because of this formulation, Pannenberg asserts that there will be no further Self-revelation of God after the resurrection of Jesus.[93]

 


251

But this thesis also lacks conclusive evidence. Indeed, it raises several problems of its own. For instance, if revelation is mediated in all of history as Pannenberg claims, why should the indirect Self-revelation of God then end with the fate of Christ? Why should revelation not extend beyond this point? One could still hold that the supreme Self-revelation of God occurred in the Christ event, but that this revelation still progresses beyond this point. Is not Pannenberg's abrupt halt at the fate of Jesus a rather arbitrary termination of revelation? Indeed, it does appear to be simply a desired stopping point. But there is obviously a need for a logical reason to support such an abrupt halt. Pannenberg entertains this same objection at the end of his introductory essay, stating that he hopes this problem will be answered later.[94] But he never quite seems to come back to it with an appropriate answer.

Even if Pannenberg were successful in showing why revelation should end here, would it not then demand an adjustment in his previous concept of this revelation? It would appear that the previous notion that God's indirect Self-disclosure occurs in all of history--in everything that happens[95]--must be revised. How can one assert that everything which occurs is revelation and then later arbitrarily drop this notion after the Christ event becomes past history? Logically, according to Pannenberg's system, revelation should continue past this point.

A closely related problem with this fourth thesis is that if God's revelation occurs in all events of human history, why single out one   


252

strand, namely Jewish history, in which to concentrate almost all attention? To do so favors the Biblical witness, to be sure, but what is the rationale behind such an assertion if one begins with Pannenberg's presuppositions? As Daniel Fuller aptly points out, Pannenberg must deal with the problem of how God reveals Himself in all of history and yet all of the most important revelation occurs especially to a select group of Jews and Christians.[96]

Also, since God is said to act in all of history, how can one ascertain when He acts in a special way in just one event like the fate of Jesus? Some may look at an event and see God working, others may look at the same event and not notice this at all.[97] Perhaps these points indicate that Pannenberg's view of revelation occurring in all of history needs adjustment.

It is therefore possible to perceive areas of Pannenberg's theological system which contain several inadequately supported assertions. These problems seem especially related to his view of the future and how it affects the present. Pannenberg's statements are not self-authenticating.[98] Yet he often fails to provide reasonable facts to back his claims. As a result, this theology remains quite problematical in that the logical demonstration in key areas is often lacking.

The fourth major criticism of Pannenberg concerns both his view of the nature of the resurrection appearances of Jesus and his treatment of the naturalistic alternative views. During a discussion   

 


253

of the historicity of this event, to which we will return briefly below, Pannenberg introduces his conception of the appearances of Jesus to the disciples and to Paul. For this scholar, the resurrection appearances involved several elements. Thos who saw the resurrected Jesus saw a spiritual body, not a natural, earthly one. This appearance was accompanied by an audition and, at least in the case of Paul, a phenomenon of light. These were appearances from heaven and were recognized by all as the risen Lord.[99]

However, Pannenberg asserts that these appearances of Jesus were not very palpable ones. The nature of these occurrences were more similar to "objective visions", or visions which were not produced by the subjective consciousness of those perceiving the phenomena. In other words, the appearances of the resurrected Jesus were realities outside of the apostles in spite of a lack of corporeal qualities.[100] Pannenberg specifically opposes the subjective vision theory,[101] which makes the resurrection a concept in the minds of the disciples with no objective reality. His contentious against this view were presented above. The resurrection was rather an objective reality showing the disciples that Jesus was alive. As such it was an actual historical event.[102]

In spite of Pannenberg's more than adequate defense of the historicity of the resurrection, his stance against more objective appearance of Jesus is unwarranted. Pannenberg appears to feel that   

 


254

it is essential to choose between Paul and the gospels when discussing the nature of the resurrection body. Since he conceives of all the appearances being of a similar nature, Jesus must have always appeared as he did to Paul.[103]

It has been shown above that both the gospels and Paul maintain that Jesus' resurrected body was both similar to and different from his natural body. The emphasis in the gospels on the disciples' ability to touch Jesus' body and to otherwise verify his appearances to them has also been discussed above. This evidence in the gospels will therefore not be studied here again.[104] but the gospels also reveal the conviction that Jesus' body was somehow changed, having new qualities and powers.[105]

Paul's testimony is likewise that the resurrection body is a "spiritual body" different from one's physical body.[106] and not simply the resuscitation of a spirit. This is recognized by most theologians   

 


255

today.[107] As William H. Johnson correctly contends, theological justice must be done to both words in the Pauline phrase "spiritual body". Neither word must be over-stressed at the expense of the other. Thus, Jesus did not rise as a spirit or in a physical body, but as a spiritual body.[108]

Yet, it is not recognized as often that Paul also gives some evidence for objective appearances of Jesus. Although he possessed a new body, the Jesus who appeared to the disciples and Paul was the same Jesus who died on the cross and was afterwards buried.[109] Another indicator of the objectivity of Jesus' appearances was that he appeared to many on different occasions (see I Cor. 15:5-8). It is especially Jesus' appearance to the 500 people at once (verse six) which helps us to determine how objective these experiences were for the disciples. It is this appearances in particular which points to an objective manifestation. Paul's conception of Jesus' resurrection body was such that it could be seen by a group this size. It would therefore appear to require more than just a mystifying light and   

 


256

auditory phenomenon, along with an objective vision.[110]

Ladd also disagrees with Pannenberg's conception of "objective visions", which pattern all of Jesus' appearances after the one to Paul. The evidence shows that the gospels were written under the influence and control of various eyewitnesses of these events. There must be an underlying factual tradition behind these reports as well. Besides, once it is granted that Jesus actually rose from the dead, there is no reason why he could not have appeared various ways to various individuals.[111]

To reinforce this last statement, one must remember that, in the books of Luke-Acts, the author Luke does not seem to be aware of any contradiction in recording both the more objective appearances to the disciples and the more "spiritual" conversion appearance to Paul.[112] Similarly, many theologians also feel that the witness of the gospels is essentially compatible with that of Paul, in spite of the different stresses in each. The conclusion often is therefore that Jesus appeared in an objective way that could be verified, but in a new spiritual body.[113]

It is somewhat surprising that Pannenberg does not place even more stress than he does on the objectivity of Jesus' appearances.   

 


257

For the reasons just outlined here, it is therefore with good evidence that this fourth major criticism of Pannenberg remains valid. Eyewitness testimony witnessed to these objective appearances through such men as Luke (cf. Luke 1:1-4 with Luke 24:36-45; Acts 1:3). Such eyewitness testimony which has already been shown to exist behind the gospel traditions therefore reflects valid witness to the objectiveness of Jesus' appearances to the disciples. Even Paul refers to the original disciples' testimony of the resurrection appearances (I Cor. 15:11-15). The testimony of the gospels is thus compatible with Paul.

The second part of this fourth criticism concerns Pannenberg's treatment of the naturalistic theories which have been proposed against the resurrection. Apart from his criticism of the subjective vision theory, his overall treatment of the other alternative theories is not entirely complete. He is still successful in refuting the other hypotheses, but he fails to disprove them as sufficiently as is possible. This is an important point, for since all of Christianity rests upon the validity of the resurrection, as was determined earlier, then refutations of rival views must be as complete as possible in order to more clearly ascertain if the event actually occurred. It is especially important to the validity of this third solution to the resurrection (that this event can be demonstrated) that there are no probable solutions other than Jesus' resurrection from the dead. This therefore points to the need for as thorough as investigation and refutation of the major naturalistic theories as is possible. In addition, it is true that the more thorough such a refutation of the alternate views is, the more convincing the resulting probability of the resurrection of Jesus is made.

 


258

Wolfhart Pannenberg has built a theological system which contains many intriguing and interesting ideas. However, his work has been shown to fall prey to four major criticisms. First, his view of God as being fully revealed only in the future is an arbitrary one which lacks the proper evidence. The Scriptures, including Jesus, do not unanimously refer to God this way at all. Second, Pannenberg's view of God's indirect Self-revelation as occurring only in historical acts in only a part of the Biblical presentation of revelation. It was found the God also revealed Himself directly through the prophets and through the written word of God.

Third, the overall theological system of this scholar lacked conclusive evidence in several places. This is especially true with regard to Pannenberg's seven theses. There was a decided lack of evidence needed to demonstrate such items as the futurity of revelation and the end of all Self-revelation of God occurring in the Christ-event. Fourth, it was shown that Pannenberg's concept of the nature of the resurrection appearances was not objective enough and did not allow properly fore the evidence for more objective manifestations of Jesus. In addition, his refutation of the naturalistic theories against the resurrection was not as complete as it should have been.[114]

  


259

It is easily perceived that the resurrection of Jesus is one of the central concepts in Pannenberg's theological system. The examination of the resurrection is also the strongest aspect of his theology. His treatment of this event has been dealt with above, but a few comments are in order here. Pannenberg logically investigates the resurrection with regard to its historicity. Rival theories which seek to explain this event naturalistically are entertained and dispelled, even though such procedures are not as complete as they should have been.[115] Anyone who disputes the claim that Jesus rose from the dead is welcome--in fact, required--to arrive at an alternative theory which is adequate enough to account for the facts.[116]

It is Pannenberg's conviction that when one conducts such an investigation of the facts, one arrives at the probability that the resurrection did, indeed, occur in actual human history. An examination of the facts reveals the probable conclusion that Jesus did rise from the dead after the crucifixion. The resurrection is thus demonstrated to be an actual historical event.[117] In this conclusion Pannenberg is thorough and difficult to refute.[118] his own refutation is the most probable solution. Therefore, this conclusion appears to be quite valid.

 


260

Chapter X. Possibility Number Three: Other Similar Views

Other scholars besides Pannenberg also hold that Jesus rose literally from the dead and that this can be demonstrated to be the most probable conclusion in this issue.[1] This is surely not to affirm that these scholars followed Pannenberg in these conclusions, for most have not derived their inspiration from him, nor do they consider themselves part of the "theology of hope" school of thought. Therefore one finds that the techniques vary here, but the final result is similar.

One such theologian who believes that Jesus' literal resurrection from the dead can be demonstrated to be the most probable conclusion is Daniel Fuller. In his work Easter Faith and History, Fuller surveys most of the major theological approaches to the question off the relationship between faith and history. As the title of this work suggests, this question is surveyed particularly by examining the various views of the resurrection.

Beginning with Enlightenment rationalism and continuing through present contemporary theology, this scholar investigates most of the major theologians and their views scholar investigates most of the major theologians and their views of the historical and rational content of faith. After viewing of the historical and rational content of faith. After viewing the attempts of the major theological schools to accept the resurrection as fact from three different   

 


261

standpoints. Attempts to hold belief in this event apart from historical reasoning, by partial historical reasoning and totally by historical reasoning are then investigated. Fuller's conclusion is that none of these views are entirely acceptable, as each falls prey to various criticisms which he presents.[2] It should be noted that Fuller does agree with the principle of historical verification of the resurrection, as will be shown below. But he objects here to these methods by which such attempts are made.

Fuller's solution is to examine the first century approach to the resurrection of Jesus which is taken by Luke in the New Testament work Luke-Acts.[3] After reviewing several key hypotheses concerning the theme of Luke-Acts,[4] Fuller sets forth what he believes is the major theme of these two books.[5]

The Lukan prologue (Luke 1:1-4) sets forth some key information concerning the intentions of the author. Here Luke claims that he received the information in this work from the original eyewitnesses (Luke 1:2). Fuller points out that while Luke was thus not himself an eyewitness of Jesus' ministry, he received the information from those who did originally participate in the events.[6] However, Luke did share first hand in the fulfillment of the resurrection event,   


262

namely, the mission of the Christian church to the Gentiles. Luke therefore experienced the result if the resurrection faith firsthand.[7]

Fuller finds that an important emphasis in Luke-Acts is Luke's writing so that his readers[8] could know the certainty of what had transpired in the life of Christ and especially in his resurrection. In fact, Luke's purpose in writing to these early believers was to inform them that they would be sure of what had been reported to them pertaining to the Christ event. This certainty which was available to each reader applied in particular to the surety that Jesus was raised from the dead (see Luke 1:4).[9]

Upon what was such certainty based? Fuller explains that for Luke, the early Christian mission to the Gentiles was the fulfillment of the resurrection of Jesus. Without the appearances to the disciples and the others and later to Paul, there could have been no such Gentile mission. In other words, the existence and continuance of the effort to evangelize the Gentiles depended upon the ministry of Paul and upon the authority and action of the other apostles. But Paul's involvement in such a work cannot be explained by anything other than the appearance of the risen Jesus to him, as recorded in Acts. Paul, the enemy and persecutor of the church in earlier years,   

 


263

would have no other impetus for such behavior. Likewise, the disciples were not very accustomed to the idea of taking the gospel to the Gentiles (at least in the form of a ministry) until they received just such a commission from the risen Lord who appeared to them after his death. Only such an appearance could account for their realizing that the offer of the Kingdom of God had also been extended to the Gentiles.[10]

In a sense, Luke taught that there were therefore two key points in the present which pointed backwards to the resurrection. First, Paul's conversion could be explained no other way than his having seen the risen Jesus. No other conclusion is sufficient to account for this change in the life of a non-believing enemy of the early church.[11] Second, the outreach of the early Jews to the Gentiles, spearheaded by the disciples, pointed to the directive beyond the exclusivism of Judaism. Apart from the directive issued by the risen Jesus,[12] there is no other probable reason for the Jewish mission to the Gentiles, since the Jews considered themselves as the sole theirs of God's blessings.[13] Therefore, these two events point unequivocally to the historical resurrection of Jesus.[14]

 


264

For these reasons, Luke stood at a critical point in that he was both able to receive knowledge of the Christ event of the past via the eyewitnesses and also to participate in the present and future fulfillment of this event. From his vantage point he realized that the resurrection was the only logical explanation for occurrences sich as the conversion of Paul and the Jewish outreach to the Gentiles with the gospel. Thus he encouraged Theophilus and his other readers to reason from these two events in the present to the resurrection of Jesus in the past, realizing that the present reality could only be explained by the factualness of the past event.[15]

After presenting Luke's position here, Fuller is careful to point out that the resurrection is the solution to these two present events only if the objections against the resurrection have been answered.[16] Earlier he entertained various alternate theories against the historical and verifiable nature of this event.[17] At this point, after a presentation of Luke's attempts to show that the resurrection was verifiable,[18] Fuller turns to the question of Paul's conversion. Alternate theories to explain this event are also investigated and   

 


265

refuted.[19]

Fuller's final investigation deals with Luke's arguments for the historicity of the resurrection. For Luke, history is view as having two sections, an "upper" and a "lower". In the first or lower section, all historical events are "natural" ones, as they originate from other historical events. But Supernatural events from the second, or higher section, do enter the first. These events could never be the results of occurrences in the first section, but to enter the first from the second "layer". Here they do not disturb other events, but also follow the patterns of history in the first section after they enter. Thus, for Luke, the resurrection can have a Supernatural origin and still be a historical event, known by historical reasoning.[20]

Luke's approach is found to be quite satisfying, according to Fuller. He agrees with Luke that the resurrection of Jesus can be verified. Given the possibility of believing in this event apart from historical reasoning or in holding that it is based upon evidences that can be historically verified, Fuller opts for the latter. The resurrection can be shown to be a historical event, both be the investigation of the original eyewitness testimony concerning the appearances and by viewing the fulfillment of this event in history in the conversion of Paul and in the Gentile mission. Belief in this event is thus based upon empirical claims.[21]

 


266

Fuller's approach to the resurrection sometimes appears to reach overly easy conclusions. This is most evident in his refutation of alternate view both with regard to Jesus' resurrection and in the appearance to Paul. Fuller desires to explore such theories[22] and does refute the major alternatives, as shown above. But the various refutations often appear irresolute and are generally, as with Pannenberg, not as thorough and strong as should be expected. As noted above, it is imperative that the alternative view are refuted as completely as possible in order to reveal if there is a probable naturalistic answer to the resurrection faith, which is rightly viewed as the central tenet of Christianity. It follows that the more thoroughly these alternative hypotheses are refuted, the more probable the resurrection becomes.

It is also possible that Fuller depends too much on the Gentile mission as demonstrating the resurrection, almost as if this conclusion could stand apart from any other investigation of the facts and alternate theories. It must be stressed once again that the Gentile mission can be a pointer to the resurrection only if other objectives to this event are completely answered. Fuller does recognize this, but seems to neglect the conclusion that of a valid alternate theory to the resurrection is found, a valid alternate theory would also have to be applied to the Gentile mission. We once again perceive the need to refute alternative theories as completely as possible.

 


267

In spite of these criticisms, however, it is most difficult to annul Fuller's contention that the resurrection can be demonstrated. He does provide enough evidence to establish this event as probable. In so doing he avoids the pitfalls of Pannenberg's theological system and still succeeds in showing how the literal resurrection of Jesus can be verified as a historical event.

Another theologian who likewise concludes that Jesus' resurrection is the best explanation for the facts is New Testament scholar George E. Ladd.[23] This scholar realizes that the modern concept of historical methodology argues for a reality in which God does not act in human history. Ever since the Enlightenment, the prevailing view has been that historical event must have origins which are grounded in history. Therefore, miracles with Supernatural origins are ruled out from the outset.[24]

In opposition to this view, Ladd proposes the use of the inductive method of historical inquiry, which allows for the conclusion which best fits the facts. Historical events which claim Supernatural intervention must be investigated to perceive if they are the best explanations for what is known to have occurred. Possible alternative theories must also be examined to see if these hypotheses are able to better account for the factual evidence.[25]


268

In the case of the resurrection of Jesus, Ladd points out that even if this occurrence were established as an actual event, it must still be counted as "nonhistorical" with regards to its origin. Since such an event would require a Supernatural origin, it could not be said to be historical in the sense that other events are, whose starting point is history itself.[26] Therefore, when judged by modern historical methodology, the resurrection is not a historical event. It is unlike other events in its unique entrance into history.[27]

However, looking at the resurrection only from the standpoint of its origin yields only a portion of the overall picture. For Ladd, historical inquiry cannot prove the resurrection, but it can establish it as the most probable explanation for what occurred. In fact, it is asserted that this event is the only explanation of the facts which adequately explains what is know to have happened.[28]

The belief that this event can be demonstrated to be the only possible solution which accounts for all of the facts is based upon the idea that there must be an adequate explanation for any event occurring in history.[29] To this end, Ladd enumerates the core historical facts surrounding the resurrection which are known to be credible.[30] Later he investigates the major alternative theories   

 


269

which seek to account for these facts by naturalistic means. Each is examined and critiqued. Ladd concludes that each theory fails to explain these resurrection facts.[31]

It should briefly be noted however, that one of the same problems which appears in Pannenberg and Daniel Fuller is also apparent in Ladd with regard to the naturalistic theories of the resurrection. Although Ladd provides a good critique of the subjective and objective vision theories and generally does better overall job here than Fuller, his treatment of the other theories is not developed thoroughly enough. In fact, the other theories are said to need very little refutation.[32] This lack of a more complete refutation is very important in that is must be ascertained as thoroughly as possible if the resurrection actually happened--if this Supernatural event is more probable than other explanations. The resurrection can be shown to be more probable when other alternate theories are more thoroughly shown to be less so.

As pointed out above, the explanation which best accounts for the historical facts is the one which is given the status of probability. Here Ladd arrive at the conclusion that Jesus' resurrection from the dead is the most probable explanation. It gives the most adequate explanation to the available facts. The only reason to reject this conclusion is that one has a closed mind to the occurrence of the Supernatural.[33]


270

Thus, while the resurrection differs from other occurrences in that if has a different origin into the historical processes, it is nevertheless an event in history. It therefore achieves the status of entering the historical process by means of a nonhistorical, Supernatural origin but still becoming a historical event.[34]

Ladd offers a logical approach to the resurrection which seeks to examine the most probable conclusion to this issue. However, he comes perilously close to making some of the some mistakes as did Karl Barth.

It has been state that Ladd explains the resurrection as being nonhistorical in that it enters history Supernaturally. Because of this origin, this event is not historical in the same sense as other events. Therefore, if evaluated in terms of the modern concept of history, the resurrection is not a historical fact.[35]

But Ladd moves even closer to Barth's position at other points. For instance, he concludes that even though the resurrection can be shown to be the best historical explanation for what occurred, it is still primarily perceptible to the "eye of faith". Thus, a historian looking at this event can only ascertain that something wonderful happened. The conclusion that Jesus was risen remains a tenet of faith. In fact, it is Ladd's opinion that even having actually seen the risen Jesus would still not prove the facticity of this event.[36]   

 


271

The appearances thus speak of the need for faith to approach this event.[37]

Admittedly, Ladd's position does differ from Barth's in other major facets. Unlike Barth, Ladd opts for investigating the historical evidence for the resurrection.[38] There is therefore an interaction between history and faith, as faith is logical and not simple a leap in the dark.[39] Also unlike Barth, Ladd admits that his faith would be seriously affected if an alternate theory were found to be plausible. Thus he takes considerable effort to refute the leading alternate theories against the resurrection.[40]

Probably the biggest difference with Barth is Ladd's contention that the resurrection can be demonstrated to be the most probable explanation for the facts. The only logical conclusion is that Jesus actually rose from the dead in history. Other naturalistic theories are found to be unacceptable. Here one finds that faith is reinforced   

 


272

by studying the evidences.[41] Barth opposed all such historical reasoning as an assistance to faith.[42]

In spite of the differences between these two theologians (especially Ladd's emphasis on the ability to demonstrate that the resurrection is the most probable conclusion), Ladd is still guilty of treating to the concept of metahistory when confronted be modern historiography. In so doing, history is split into two divisions--the secular and the divine.[43] As mentioned with regards to Barth, history knows of no such differentiation and no such concept of prehistory. Montgomery points out that by making the resurrection a part of this questionable realm of history and by asserting that it can be known primarily by faith, Ladd makes this event only perceptible in an meaningful way to the believer. Thus the non-Christian is not able to benefit from the evidence in favor of this event.[44]

Ladd's concern with pointing out that the resurrection would require a Divine origin has been noted above. But one can recognize that the origin of this event is Supernatural and still not resort to the concept of metahistory. Daniel Fuller[45] and C.S. Lewis,[46] for   

 


273

instance, have both done creditable jobs in showing how an event can have a Supernatural origin and still be normally connected with history once it enters the historical process. Thus, the matter of Divine causation should not automatically determine that the event must be metahistorical and that it must be known only be the processes of faith. Once it enters history, this event could partake of the historical pattern without impeding other natural events. Therefore, in spite of the origin of a Suerpnatural miracle, it would become a historically verifiable event upon entering history.

To agree with Barth (and others) in holding that a Supernatural event remains metahistorical even after it enters the historical process is, once again to divde history into the two component parts of the secular and the divine. But, as has been pointed out in the critique of Barth in chapter eight, this formulation is faulty. The criticisms directed against Barth will not be repeated here, as it has been sufficiently shown that such a concept is not valid.

To be sure, Ladd accepts critical examinations of the Christian faith. He believes that the inductive historical approach which accepts the event which best fits the evidence will demonstrate that the resurrection actually did occur.[47] Here he differs from Barth. But where Ladd does adopt Barth's metahistorical concept,[48] it must   

 


274

be agreed that he errs in committing some of the same mistakes as Barth. It the Supernatural is found to occur it must happen in historically verifiable history and not in metahistory. This is recognized by Pannenberg, Daniel Fuller, Lewis, and others.[49]

Ladd does not retreat completely into the realm of metahistory as does Barth. His emphasis on being able to demonstrate the resurrection is therefore, like the attempts of Pannenberg and Fuller, a positive aspect of his theology. All three theologians have succeeded investigating the facts before arriving at a final solution and all three scholars have found the resurrection to be the most probable explanation of what occurred. These findings are further strengthened by the failure of any naturalistic theories to adequately account for what happened.

However, it is not only certain theologians who are convinced of this conclusion. Paul Maier is an ancient historian who also believes that the resurrection is the most probably answer for what occurred.[50] Although Maier is not the only historian to reach such conclusions,[51]  

 


275

his approach is probably the most thorough from the standpoint of historical studies.[52]

Maier, the discipline of history is very valuable in helping to ascertain what occurred on the first Easter morning. While many ancient historical events are based upon only one source, and two sources often render an event "infallible", these are several ancient sources which point to the even of the resurrection of Jesus.[53] Even outside of the New Testament sources, there is important extrabiblical evidence especially for the empty tomb, and thus also for the resurrection.[54]

Maier points to such early historians as Tacitus and Josephus, who either infer or specifically mention the belief in the resurrection on on the part of the disciples and the early church. Tacitus' reference to first century Christianity in Rome and to the "superstition" which broke out in Judea after the death of Jesus[55] is perceived in imply the Christian teaching of the resurrection of Jesus.[56] Maier also deals with the problem of a possible interpolation in Josephus' more specific reference to the resurrection of Jesus[57] and find that there   

 


276

is very good reason to believe that Josephus did compose this statement concerning Christ minus a few of the more "Christianize" phrases. Thus we see that, in all probability, Josephus reported the early Christian belief in the resurrection and thereby acknowledge that the tomb was empty.[58]

The evidence presented by Josephus and implied by Tacitus is further corroborated by a few other sources. In the first century it was reported that the Jews spread the story that the disciples stole the body of Jesus in order to proclaim his resurrection from the dead. It is related that this story was still being voiced in   

 


277

the second half of the first century.[59] In formulating this totally inadequate view, the Jews not only did not succeed in offering a substantial objection to the resurrection, but in so doing they also admitted the empty tomb.

This Scriptural report is confirmed by second century scholar Justin Martyr, who reports in his Dialogue with Trypho (about 150 A.D.) that the Jews sent specially taught men across the Mediterranean Sea in order to counter the Christian claims of the resurrection. The explanation spread abroad by the Jews, once again, was that the disciples stole their dead Master's body. The Jews therefore continued to admit the empty tomb.[60]

 


278

As pointed out be Maier, the book of Acts gives further evidence that the tomb was empty on the first Easter morning. As the disciples and early Christians first began to proclaim the resurrection of Jesus from the dead, the Jewish authorities objected strenuously. But in several confrontations with the disciples, the Jewish elders never did what might have been most expected--they never led the disciples to the tomb for an investigation. Discovering the body of Jesus would of course have destroyed Christianity, as the Jewish leader desired to do anyway. The obvious reason that they did not try to locate the body is because they knew that the tomb was empty. Maier asserts that even the impartial historian must admit this historical evidence for the empty tomb.[61] This implicit admission further pointed to the empty tomb mentioned y Josephus. Matthew, Justin Martyr and also implied by Tacitus.

Maier also utilizes circumstantial evidence of two kinds. First, Christianity could not have had its beginnings at Jerusalem, as it did, if Jesus' grave was still occupied just outside the gates of the city. This is the last place that the church could have begun if Jesus' body was still in the tomb. Here an investigation of the   

 


279

grave would have revealed the body and Christianity would have been destroyed before it really began. The birth of the church in Jerusalem can only be explained by the fact that Jesus' tomb was indeed empty.[62]

Second, the spread of Christianity around the Mediterranean region all the way to Rome itself by slightly after the first half of the first century is simply an astonishing feat to have been accomplished in so short a period of time. Approximately thirty years after the death of Jesus this amazing expansion had taken place. It is Maier's view that such expansion of any teaching or philosophy is unparalleled in ancient times. Could the preaching of and belief in the resurrection have provided the impetus for such growth, as the New Testament attests?[63]

Another piece of evidence has only a possible connection directly with Jesus' resurrection. A valuable archaeological discovery revealed a marble slab found in Nazareth which contained a warning from Caesar to all who were caught robbing graves in Palestine. Other such Roman edicts against grave robbing prescribed a fine against the offender, whereas this edict condemns the offender to capital punishment. Most scholars believed that the inscription was the command of emperor Tiberius or emperor Claudius. Why was the punishment   

 


280

to be so great in Palestine? Could this command have been prompted by the Jewish report of Jesus' stolen body or by the preaching of the resurrection?[64]

Theological evidence is also cited by Maier in his effort to deal historically with the resurrection. This historian points to at least three other factors which lead to the final conclusion. First, the aforementioned change in the disciples caused them to believe that Jesus had risen from the dead. Such a radical difference must be based upon some real experience and points to an actual encounter with the risen Lord, just as the New Testament claims. Second, the very existence of the Church points to some event which is worthy of such an enterprise. The New Testament claims this event was the resurrection. Third, there must have been a reason for the early church to have changed the day of meeting from Saturday, the Jewish Sabbath, to Sunday, the Lord's day. Again, the New Testament claims that the resurrection caused this change in order to commemorate that day on which Jesus had risen.[65]

The last type of evidence employed by Maier is of both a historical and theological nature. Maier entertains the objections raised by eight different naturalistic theories which are aimed at disproving the resurrection of Jesus. Each is then investigated and refuted by the available historical data. He finds that all of   


281

these naturalistic theories fail to provide a valid historical answer to what happened on the first Easter day. They must be rejected strictly on the basis of historical inquiry, as well as by theological reasoning.[66]

As for the question of discrepancies in the resurrection accounts, Maier admits that they do exist, as in the rest of the gospels. However, he holds that it is illogical to conclude that this event did not occur because of these variations. Other historical reports also contain similar discrepancies and there is no question about the events they report. For instance, the reports of the great fire of Rome offer even greater conflicts than do the resurrection accounts. Some reports claim that the entire city three sectors of the city were destroyed. There are also differences of opinion as to how the fire started. In spite of these problems, the great first of Rome is unquestionably a historical fact. In a similar way the resurrection of Jesus is also a historical fact. The various sources way the resurrection of Jesus is also a historical fact. The various sources simply point to the different traditions, all of which provide evidence that Jesus actually rose from the dead.[67]

Maier concludes that the will not to believe has kept many from accepting the historical evidence on the question of the resurrection.[68] The empty tomb is found definitely to be a datum of history according   

 


282

to the laws of historical research.[69] This conclusion is even strengthened by the "hostile evidence" which has been presented here. The strongest type of historical evidence is facts which are stated about an event by a source which is hostile to that event. When such a source claims that an event is factual when it is not advantageous to do so, this fact is in all probability a genuine one. The empty tomb is attested directly or indirectly by Josephus, Tacitus and by the witness of Matthew, Luke (Acts) and Justin Martyr as to Jewish practice with regards to the resurrection. Such Jewish and Roman evidence is hostile evidence, for it was not advantageous to either the Jews or to the Romans to acknowledge the empty tomb. Other historical and theological evidence, circumstantial and otherwise, has also pointed to this fact. Therefore it can be asserted that the empty tomb is historical fact.[70]

From the empty tomb Maier then argues to the probability if the resurrection. Evidence such as that presented above (especially the threefold theological proof and the refutation of the naturalistic theories) points to the resurrection of Jesus. The historical evidence is not as strong as that for the empty tomb, but the evidence on the periphery of this event points to the probability that the event itself is historical.[71]


283

Maier has added a very valuable dimension to the study of the resurrection of Jesus in that he has pursued this subject from the standpoint of history. He thus approaches this question from the standpoint of the historian looking at theology. In his work, then, Maier certainly does not look at this question as one for theology only. Yet he arrives at the conclusion that the empty tomb and resurrection are historical events according to all probability.

Admittedly, his treatment of the naturalistic theories and refutation of them could have been developed more. It has already been shown above how important a complete refutation of alternative theories is in order to more fully determine how probable the resurrection is in actuality. Maier does a fairly creditable job in this respect, but still does not treat these naturalistic hypotheses as thoroughly as is possible.

Perhaps some well object that his treatment of the theological question did not deal with theology enough. Yet this letter criticism does not rightfully allpy since his whole purpose is to approach this event as a historian and not as a theologian. Thus he cannot be judged for this second point.

Therefore, his overall effort has been a very successful one. He has logically and historically shown that naturalistic theories do not solve the historically shown that naturalistic theories do not solve the historical needs on the one hand and that valid historical pointers to the resurrection do exist on the other hand.[72] This   


284

combination makes a strong case for the historicity of the resurrection.[73]

After investigating the claims of three scholars who believe that the resurrection can be demonstrated, it must be concluded that the position of Daniel Fuller, Ladd and Maier are positive in their overall approaches and conclusions. We have found that these three also present some difficulties. However, a logical approach that is both historical and theological reveals that these portions are better supported by the evidence than the others which were discussed earlier. It yet remains for us to finally ascertain if this third possibility of demonstrating the resurrection is the one that best fits the facts.

 


285

 

PART 3

An Evaluation of the Solutions to the
Question of the Resurrection of Jesus


286

Chapter XI. An Evaluation of Possibility Number One

Chapters five and six investigated the possibility that the resurrection of Jesus did not actually occur. In chapter five it was shown that the most influential position here was held by historian and philosopher David Hume. His essay "Of Miracles" set the stage for other views which also rejected the resurrection as an event, usually because it was held that such events were impossible from the outset because they contradict the laws of nature.

It was apparent especially in chapter six that Protestant liberalism followed Hume in this position. In fact, John Herman Randall Jr. explains that Protestant liberalism as a whole followed Hume in this line reasoning. Hume's influence extended not only to the nineteenth century liberals, but also on to this present day where men of this theological persuasion have often continued to reject the miraculous, based upon this essay.[1]

Other scholars also note that Hume's essay became the definitive stance for liberalism with regards to all miracles. Smith agrees with Randall in this assertion.[2] Montgomery likewise affirms the fact that both nineteenth and twentieth century theology derived its belief in the impossibility of miracles from Hume.[3]


287

 It is interesting that these liberal theologians themselves also acknowledged that their views were based upon the stance taken by Hume. For instance, in nineteenth century liberalism, David Strauss was explicitly willing to acknowledge this dependence. For this scholar, Hume's essay had forever settled the question of the miraculous. Supernatural, nature-contradicting miracles simply do not occur.[4]

Other liberals also followed the position taken by Strauss in that they also favored Hume's position against miracles. Friedrich Schleiermacher, like Hume, asserted that miracles are found where there it little knowledge of the laws of nature. Miracles actually oppose nature and the idea of the miraculous must be abandoned.[5] Heinrich Paulus likewise followed Hume in believing that miracles are usually said to have occurred where there is a deficient knowledge of nature. Scripture is mistaken in claiming that miracles did occur and when the workings of nature are revealed, this mistake becomes even clearer.[6] which break the laws of nature.[7] For Ernst Renan, Jesus believed that miracles were common, not because they actually were, but because he was unfamiliar with the uniformity of nature's   

 


288

laws.[8]

 Later in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, liberal theologians were still following Hume and his reasons for rejecting miracles. Otto Pfleiderer held a notion that was very common, especially since Hume--that the events of nature follow an unchanging regularity and order.[9] Adolf von Harnack added his voice to the growing list of scholars who accepted, along with Hume, the belief that ancient people believed the miraculous because they did not understand the laws of nature. They did not realize that events which interrupt nature never occur. Thus, miraculous cannot be believed.[10]

In the twentieth century, as mentioned above, liberal theologians continued to accept Hume's position on miracles as the definitive one. Rudolf Bultmann accepts the view for miracles. Because of the natural laws, the universe is closed to Supernatural workings. Thus miracles are no longer acceptable in today's world.[11] For Paul Tillich, no events such as miracles can break the laws of nature.[12] John A.T. Robinson holds that the Biblical miracles are myths because natural processes cannot be interrupted by God's intervention. The New Testament    

 


289

cosmology must therefore be abandoned.[13]

It is quite obvious from this foregoing survey that both nineteenth and twentieth century liberal theologians have followed Hume in rejecting all possibility for the miraculous. That Hume was the primary inspiration for this viewpoint is also pain.

Yet it has been shown above that Hume's thesis failed to provide an adequate prohibitive against the occurrence of miracles. Four major objections were raised against this view. Briefly, it was first discovered that Hume utilized a series of logical errors, especially circular reasoning and begging the question. This is especially noticeable in his definition of miracle and in his assumption of the negative value of all experience of miracles, when just such an investigation value of all experience might demonstrate the probability of a miracle. Second, Hume arbitrarily rejects miracles even where he recognizes a high credibility for the Supernatural event described. Third, Hume rejects miracles because of a faulty view of the uniformity of nature which he himself had rejected in other works. This incorrect view of nature is the center of his polemic and must therefore be rejected. Fourth, in spite of Hume's agreements with modern thought in several aspects of his work, he reverted to a pre-modern stance with respect to his view of miracles. Although he rejected the then popular view of a closed universe and opted for the use of probabilities, he inconsistently rejected miracles from the outset because they were believed to be impossible. He also ignored any probabilities for   

 


290

miracles and thus ruled them out in a way which is not consistent with the above modern concepts which he accepted. Here he is pre-modern and in error.[14]

All ten of the theologians just surveyed also agree in accepting the view that the universe is closed to all occurrences of Supernatural miracles. These events are generally conceived of as being impossible because they oppose the workings of nature. Ancient people who accepted such reports as true were often said to have done so because they did not understand nature properly.[15] It is therefore more possible to verify the contention of Randall, Montgomery and Smith given above that all of liberalism as a whole followed Hume in these conclusions.[16] J. Gresham Machen concurs with these scholars that liberalism did indeed agree in abandoning belief in the miraculous.[17]

Because both nineteenth and twentieth century liberalism followed Hume's reasoning in its rejection of the miraculous, it is thus possible to ascertain that these theologians were, like Hume, also in error concerning these views. For these reasons it is not surprising to find that almost the same criticisms of Hume which were related in    


291

chapter five with regard to the use of improper presuppositions and an incorrect methodology and concerning the use of a faulty view of the uniformity of nature also apply to these other scholars. As Hume was found to be in error in these concepts, so also is liberal theology likewise in error here. Miracles cannot be ruled out be such an approach.

A second indication that the method employed by theological liberalism since Hume's time is in error concerns the naturalistic theories which have been suggested in order to account for the resurrection of Jesus. Such hypotheses were necessary in order to account for the resurrection of Jesus. Such hypotheses were necessary in order to explain an event which had already been reject a la Hume. The major theories which have been formulated against the resurrection have been discussed above and refuted.[18] An investigation of each demonstrated that they could not properly account for what is known to have occurred. Each can be adequately refuted historically, logically and theologically.[19]

That none of the naturalistic theories adequately accounts for the resurrection of Jesus is indeed an extremely acute point against theological liberalism's stance on the resurrection. Our endeavor has been to find the historical conclusion which is most probable--the one which best accounts for what is known to have occurred. Yet, none of even the "strongest" alternative theories is even persuasive, let alone being probable. A more adequate solution is definitely   


292

needed here.

AA third indication that the liberal theological position on the resurrection is incorrect is the fact that even those who formulated naturalistic theories against this event joined in the decimation of other "rival" theories. Thus it was shown earlier how Strauss and Renan (among others) were both strongly opposed to Paulus' swoon theory. In fact, it is usually believed that Strauss himself gave the final death-blow to the theory, which destroyed it for good. However, Strauss' vision theory was opposed strenuously be such scholars as Schleiermacher, Paulus and Keim. Once again it was a liberal theologian, Keim, who is generally considered to be the one whose liberal arguments disposed of Strauss' theory.[20]

While such opposition by these of a similar theological stance surely does not automatically prove these theories to be wrong, the indications are that each felt that the other naturalistic theories were in error. This points to a real dissatisfaction with such theories on the part of these scholars. None could convince even those of his own theological persuasion that his view was the most probable one.[21]


293

There are thus three very important reasons for holding that the answer to the resurrection which is suggested by Hume and by all of theological liberalism fails to account adequately for what is known to have occurred. First, much of the criticism directed against Hume in chapter five also applies to liberalism's approach to this event. Thus the entire methodology and the presuppositions which are used are invalid, as is the faulty view of the uniformity of nature. The resurrection and other miracles cannot properly be negated by these methods. This point alone is devastating to these positions. Second, the fact that no naturalistic theory adequately accounts for what occurred is an even stronger point against Hume and liberalism. That no probability can be established for any such alternative theory demonstrates that none of these hypotheses can be accepted as the probable solution. Third, not even those who reject the resurrection agree that any theory adequately account for the evidence. Rather, several scholars were content to destroy the arguments for theories which opposed their own, clearly revealing the inherent weaknesses of each.

It is popular in contemporary theology to deny Jesus' literal resurrection and at the same time to affirm that in some way he can still be said to be alive today. For instance, Bultmann contends that although Jesus did not actually rise from the dead,[22] he still meets us through the words of preaching as the risen Lord. Thus, while Jesus   

 


294

himself did not actually rise from the dead as the New Testament affirms, we can still encounter the risen Lord today by faith in the words which are preached. In fact it is only by this mode that the resurrection becomes present and it thereby become possible to meet the risen Jesus.[23]

Marxsen likewise accepts such a formulation. Although Jesus is dead, his offer of faith has not lost its validity[24] because Jesus lives today in the content of Christian preaching. Thus Jesus' activity continues beyond the grave. He shows himself to be alive because men still continue to respond to him in faith.[25] For Marxsen, Jesus' resurrection is thus not the raising of the dead man from the grave, but rather the crucified and dead Jesus still influencing men to believe even today.[26]  

The purpose behind such theological maneuvers is obvious. The desire is to be able to continue to teach that the Christian faith is still valid for modern man even though many are still inclined to reject the resurrection as an actual event in history. In this way traditional beliefs which in the New Testament are a result of the resurrection can be confirmed in a way that is more harmonious    

 


295

with modern thought.

However, this position is quite obviously laden with several incredibilities. There are at least two valid reasons for rejecting such a theological stance.

First, such an understanding of Jesus' resurrection, whereby he is said to be alive even though he did not literally rise from the dead, is contrary to the earliest Christian understanding of this event. The Jewish conception of resurrection involved the raising of the body. The first century Christians likewise believed in the resurrection of a spiritual body as clearly shown above, and Jesus was believed to have literally risen in this way. Therefore, to assert that this modern view is close to the New Testament is ridiculous.[27] For the earliest believers, Jesus was said to be alive at present, but because he had literally risen from the dead, not because his influence had simply continued beyond the grave in spite of being dead.

As asserted by Maier, the modern concept that the Christian faith would still be valid even is Jesus had never risen bodily would be nothing but nonsense to Paul and other first century Christians.[28] Brown agrees, adding that formulations such as Marxsen's are of little value if they do not do justice to the New Testament stance, which allows only one interpretation of the resurrection--a literal resuscitation.[29] Ladd states this well:

The New Testament knows nothing about the persistence of Jesus' personality apart from the resurrection of the body. Neither   

 


296

does the New Testament know the 'resurrection of the spirit' to heaven…It his body is mouldering in a Palestinian tomb, he cannot be the exalted Lord…[30]

Admittedly, the New Testament concept of Jesus' resurrection is not self-vindicating. But the point here is a crucial one. The testimony of Paul is that if Jesus did not rise literally in a spiritual body in such a way that he could appear to others, then he did not rise at all (I Cor. 15:1-19). This is the choice which is open to us. Either Jesus rose literally or he cannot be said to be alive in any other than in a spiritual sense. To take a middle ground which claims that Jesus is alive but that he did not rise from the dead is not open to us. The earlier Christians in particular would not recognize such a compromising belief. If Jesus was dead, Christian theology could not be true at all. If Jesus is dead, neither can contemporary theology hold to the other affirmations and doctrines of the Christian faith. They all stand or all together.

Second, logic alone dictates that this modern concept of the resurrection is valid. As Ladd firmly states, if Jesus did not rise bodily from the tomb, then he is still dead.[31] It is plain that if a person is dead he cannot still be alive unless one is speaking of spiritual immortality or of the continuation of one's personality as he is remembered by others or some such understanding. Apart from just such a resurrection as the New Testament proclaims, Jesus cannot be said to be any more alive than anyone else who has ever died. Apart from a literal resurrection, he could still be influencing people today only in the sense of the continued affect of his life and teachings upon others. But to say that Jesus is risen because of   


297

such spiritual immortality or influence is plainly illogical and inaccurate. It also involves a gross misappropriation of words.

The early Christian belief in Jesus' resurrection could not have survived if Jesus' body was still rotting in the grave.[32] In fact, no part of the Christian faith could be considered true if Jesus had never risen from the dead. Ladd states this fact quite well:

But if Jesus is dead,[33] his entire message is negated. If he is dead, he cannot come in his Kingdom and its blessings is also a delusion, for the presence of the Kingdom-blessings was but an anticipation of the eschatological Kingdom to be established by the heavenly Son of Man…If Jesus is dead, his entire message about the Kingdom of God is a delusion. If Jesus is dead, the heart of the New Testament Christology is also delusion.[34]

For these reasons, the modern formulation[35] whereby it is held that Jesus is alive even though he did not literally rise from the dead cannot be valid. Such an interpretation does not coincide with the New Testament understanding of this event and so cannot be understood as such. The New Testament presents a "do or die" attitude as regards the literal resurrection of Jesus. Only if it occurred literally can we hold Christian theology to be valid. Any other understanding of this event is therefore not possible if one still desires to embrace Christian doctrine.

 


298

In addition, this modern formulation is quite illogical. A dead man who did not rise from the dead is no more alive than any other dead individual. Such a man could only influence people by the inspiration of his past life and teachings. But such a person has not "risen" and is not alive any more than any other person. His present spiritual existence would therefore not be unique. Only by a literal resurrection can an individual be proclaimed as being risen.

Thus we must conclude that David Hume and theological liberalism as a whole (both nineteenth and twentieth century) do not offer a valid approach to the resurrection of Jesus. The methodology and presuppositions which are used have been shown to be in error, as is the correct conception of the uniformity of nature. Without these faulty premises the subsequent conclusions which were postulated against the resurrection most assuredly cannot be held. Also, the naturalistic theories which were preposed as alternate suggestions to account for the belief in the resurrection were shown to be inadequate to account for the known facts. These theories fall short historically, logically and theologically. In addition, liberal theologians themselves showed that the alternate theories were not valid by demonstrating the inadequacies of each one.

It was likewise determined that the popular modern understanding of Jesus as being "risen" and "alive" today in spite of his having never risen from the dead is also a totally inadequate conception. It must be rejected, as shown above, in that it violates the earliest Christian understanding of this event and because it is quite illogical.

It is therefore necessary that the answer given by Hume and by  

 


299

contemporary liberal theology since his time rejected as an inadequate solution to the question of the resurrection. None of the naturalistic theories are event historically plausible, let alone probable, and must therefore be abandoned. This theory that the resurrection did not occur thus fails at the crucial point of not being able to formulate a probably alternate theory of otherwise to properly rule out the resurrection. Any alternative theory such as these which have been examined and refuted here must therefore be rejected.[36]

The questions discussed in this chapter are very important ones. All of Christian theology relies on the validity of the resurrection and it is therefore imperative to understand if this event is an actual occurrence. To say that Jesus is risen or alive, but that he did not literally rise from the dead just compounds the dilemma. It is inadequate as an answer to the question of whether Jesus really rose. It is our desire to evaluate the other possibilities in order to ascertain if they can come any closer to a probable answer.

 


300

Chapter XII. And Evaluation of Possibility Number Two

In chapters seven and eight the possibility was investigated that the resurrection of Jesus actually occurred but that it cannot be demonstrated as such. It was shown in chapter seven that the most influential position here was that of theologian and philosopher Soren Kierkegaard. It also became obvious, especially in chapter eight, that many others have followed him in this belief.

It has just been found that the conclusion that the resurrection did not occur fails in that it can neither provide a probable solution to the facts or otherwise properly negate this event. Thus an answer must be found elsewhere.

Kierkegaard popularized the conclusion that the resurrection (and other miracles) actually happened, but that this event cannot be proven to have occurred. It can only be accepted by faith. It is solely by faith and not by any type of demonstration whatsoever that we come to know God.

This position was further developed by Karl Barth, who clearly accepted the resurrection as a historical event which actually occurred. But like Kierkegaard, this event cannot be proven to have occurred at all. However, Barth followed earlier theologians like Martin Kahler in relegating the resurrection to other than totally objective history. This event was believed to have occurred in a nonvarifiable type of history which is removed from objective tests such as historical investigation.

Many theologians followed Barth in these views. Today it is    

 


301

quite popular to conceive of the resurrection as a real event, but one which is not verifiable.

The rationale behind such a theory is apparently to be able to affirm the resurrection as a real event for faith but at the same time to remove this event from the critical eye of modern historiography. Thus it appears that Barth's intention (and those who agree with him) is to remove the Christian faith from this realm of modern historical methodology and thus to keep Christianity from any possibility of being critically investigated.[1] Such methods of verification are viewed as being opposed to the New Testament presentation of faith.[2]

In spite of Barth's seeming desire to "preserve" Christianity from all such critical investigations, his formulation is still quite problematical. It has already been found in chapter three above that history is required to investigate all possible facts surrounding an event in order to find the most probable conclusion. It was concluded that neither science or history can rule out the miraculous a priori. Rather, all of the facts must be thoroughly investigated with the conclusion which best supports the facts being viewed as the probable one. Therefore a miracle such as the resurrection might be found to   


302

be the probable conclusion and thus be viewed as an actual historical event. For this reason, Barth need not feel that the facts of Christianity must be preserved from historical or other types of investigation. If these facts are found to be probable they will thereby defend themselves. Otherwise such an event would not merit that faith which the New Testament asserts is dependent upon it. Barth is therefore in error in recommending such a procedure as being essential.

This last criticism of Barth's method is in addition to the other major problems which have been pointed out in chapters seven and eight with regards to both Kierkegaard's and Barth's position (and also concerning those scholars who follow them). Briefly, there were three major criticisms directed against Kierkegaard. First, even Kierkegaard himself is not successful in building a theological system that is not first built on some reasonable foundation. For instance, his polemic for faith and subjectivity is somewhat rational, as he makes use of both logic and reason. Each his convictions were shown to be rationally-based. In fact, his entire system could not be formulated apart from reason. Thus it is shown to be impossible to have faith apart from some sort of rational basis. Second, since faith is construed as being temporally first and reason is given no real place by this scholar, it is not possible to know if such faith is valid. Since there would be no objective criteria by which to examine the Christian faith, we cannot know it it is correct in its beliefs or not. Faith must therefore be testable in order to determine if it is valid. Otherwise one never ascertain whether he

 


303

was right in this faith and whether his belief was trustworthy and factual, or if it was simply spurious.[3]

From the first two criticisms of Kierkegaard it becomes apparent that 1) reason is temporally first and 2) faith needs an objective foundation so that it can be verified. A third criticism of Kierkegaard naturally follows from these first two. Since some reasonable verification is therefore needed upon which faith can be built, a historical examination of the claims of Christianity is the most likely procedure. At the rate, such a reasonable method could not be opposed since just such an objective basis is needed.[4]

From this treatment of Kierkegaard, some of the weaknesses of this proposed approach to the resurrection can be mire clearly seen. There is definitely a need for a more objective approach to this event.

In addition to the one given above, four major criticisms were also presented concerning Barth's modification of this method.[5] Briefly, the first criticism concerns Barth's development of the idea that Jesus' resurrection occurred in prehistory or parahistory. It involves a twofold critique. History knows of no such concept   

 


304

where events can occur on the boundary or outskirts of history. This realm cannot be measured by historical methods and is thus invalid. Additionally, Barth allows no verification for events in prehistory, but still insists that they are actually historical. However, actual history can be examined and investigated. It this resurrection occurred in history it must be open to such investigation or it cannot be referred to as objective history. Second, like Kierkegaard, Barth's method allows no means whereby the Christian faith can be examined. Thus once again, it cannot be determined if this faith is valid or not. To remove Christianity from any investigation is to make it so subjective that no one could actually its trustworthiness. One could not be sure whether his belief was factual.

Third, Barth accepts the death of Jesus as an event which occurred in real history in the modern sense of the word, while the resurrection is relegated to prehistory. Yet both events are believed to be revelatory. Barth is therefore illogical to declare that God does not reveal Himself in objective, verifiable events. Since He did so at the cross, He could also do so with the resurrection. Thus the resurrection could also logically be history in the modern verifiable, objective sense. The fourth criticism of Barth is that he has clearly been shown to be wrong in his belief that the New Testament does not ever try to demonstrate the resurrection. To the contrary, such a procedure occurs several times.[6] Thus he cannot claim  

 


305

Scriptural backing for his method.[7]

For the reasons stated here, this second possible solution to the resurrection also fails to account properly for the facts which are shown to be true. Admittedly, it is laden with fewer problems that the first method discussed in the last chapter. For instance, this solution is not required to offer any naturalistic alternative views concerning the resurrection. But the approach taken by Kierkegaard, Barth and others cannot adequately deal with all of the criticisms raised here and must therefore be rejected as an incorrect treatment of Jesus' resurrection.

As concluded in chapters seven and eight, Kierkegaard and Barth both agree that faith in Christ is the most important element of Christianity. The same was also found to be true in this study in chapter four above, with faith as the more crucial element being built upon a reasonable look at the facts. Therefore, their conception of faith can remain valid even thought the methodology by which they reach this conclusion is faulty. This is because the same conclusion, namely the importance of faith, can also be reached objectively.[8]

For both Kierkegaard and Barth, the center of Christianity is salvation by faith and commitment to Jesus as the Christ. Salvation   


306

is achieved when an individual is convicted that he is a sinner and experiences a complete change in his life by repentance. This spiritual experience consists of the individual trusting the death of Christ on the cross as a substitutionary death to pay for his sins and surrendering his life to God in faith as a result. Both of these theologians also stress the subsequent commitment and the changed life which will result from a genuine conversion.[9]

Because of the aforementioned study of the reason-faith relationship, these conclusions concerning the primary importance of faith must therefore be accepted as valid. They faithfully represent the New Testament position on this subject and will be found to be even more trustworthy if the resurrection is found to be an actual historical event because a firm, objective grounding will then have been given to this concept of faith.


307

Chapter XIII. An Evaluation of Possibility Number Three

The third possible solution to the resurrection of Jesus was investigated in chapters nine and ten, a solution which postulated that the resurrection actually occurred and that it can be demonstrated to be a historical event. It was determined in chapter nine that Wolfhart Pannenberg is probably the best known representative of this viewpoint. Several other scholars likewise hold this view without following Pannenberg in these conclusions. In chapter ten the views of three other key scholars who also believe that the resurrection can be demonstrated to have occurred in history were also enumerated.

Generally speaking, each of these four scholar holds that history must be investigated in order to ascertain if the resurrection occurred. All agree that one must not be prejudiced concerning what is possible or impossible in such an investigation. The only way to ascertain if a Supernatural event such as the resurrection has actually occurred is to examine the facts and then decide which conclusion best fits there facts. This conclusion is to be accepted as the most probable one and is thus to be viewed as a historical fact, even if it is a miracle.

After an examination of the available evidence, each of these four scholars arrives at the conclusion that the resurrection is the event that best explains what happened. The method varies a little between each of these men, but the primary result is the same. The facts are best explained by the resurrection and as this is the most

 


308

probable solution, it is regarded as historical fact.[1]

In spite of the logical approach taken by these scholars, some difficulties were detected in their work. This was especially true of Pannenberg's thesis. First, his concept of God was discovered to be quite arbitrary, lacking a sufficient amount of demonstration. Contrary to Pannenberg's belief, Jesus does not speak exclusively of God's working from the future. To hold such a position one must already have assumed that God works in this way in order to interpret all verses in light of this idea. This would be especially difficult with the verses which were shown to teach the opposite view. Second, in spite of Pannenberg's conception of the indirect Self-revelation of God, it was shown that the Jews also viewed revelation as occurring directly through both the spoken word of the prophets and the written word of Scripture. Thus it cannot be held that the indirect revelation of God in history was the only means of revelation accepted by the Jews.

Third, it was found that Pannenberg's overall system lacks proof a several crucial points. It is especially in the formulation of his seven theses that there is a decided lack of evidence for his views. This proclivity is perhaps best evidenced by the connection of both revelation and the fact of Jesus with the end of history. Several   


309

problems which arise as a result of these formulations were pointed out above. In fact, Pannenberg's theological framework as a whole, although interesting, sometimes lacks the demonstration needed to establish it beyond the realm of philosophical speculation. Fourth, Pannenberg's treatment of the resurrection fails in tow respects. First, he firmly accepts this occurrence as a historical event, but rejects any strongly objective appearances of Jesus even when the evidence indicates otherwise. But it was shown that such conclusions are unwarranted and that the witness of the New Testament is to the contrary. Nevertheless, this scholar does indeed believe that Jesus actually did rise from the dead and appear to his disciples.

The second part of this fourth criticism concerns Pannenberg's treatment of the naturalistic theories which have been composed in opposition to the resurrection. With the exception of the subjective vision theory, his critique of these alternate theories is not as strong as it could have been. Yet it is imperative that these naturalistic views be refuted as conclusively as possible. Since the resurrection is the central element in the Christian faith, it is essential to ascertain if this event actually occurred. Therefore, a complete refutation of the naturalistic hypotheses would allow a more accurate decision on the probability of the resurrection. Also, the more thorough the refutation of these alternate view is, the easier it is both to conclude that there are no views which are more probable than Jesus' resurrection as a historical event and the more probable the resurrection is shown to be.

It was likewise found that Daniel Fuller, Ladd and Maier also fell prey to this last criticism. Like Pannenberg, these three scholars were also successful in refuting the major alternative theories.   

 


310

But also like Pannenberg, seldom was a complete refutation given. Once again, a more thorough and entire negation of the rival views on the part of all four scholars would reveal even more positively if there were any probable solutions other than the literal resurrection of Jesus. The more complete this investigation and refutation is, the easier it is to verify that the resurrection is the most probable answer and the more probable this event itself becomes. Since all four scholars endeavor to establish the probability of this event, the object should of course be to do so as accurately and thoroughly as possible.[2]

In addition to this one common criticism made of all four of these scholars concerning their incomplete treatments of the alternate theories, other more individual criticisms were pointed out above. But in all cases, these critiques did not annul the defense of the resurrection which was presented by each of the four. In fact, it is quite difficult to annul approaches when it is realized that to successfully abrogate them, one would have to propose a more probable naturalistic solution to the resurrection.[3]

Significantly, it was not only negative evidence (such as that which was presented against the alternate theories) which was ascertained to favor the resurrection as an actual even in history. It was also shown that there were positive facts and pointers which also indicate   


311

that this is the most probable explanation of the facts. For example, Daniel Fuller points to the conversion of Paul and the existence of the Gentile mission. Maier presented historical evidence of various types to corroborate his position.

It is for these reasons that the third possible approach to the resurrection, which proposes that this event actually occurred and that it can be demonstrated, presents itself as the best solution to the question of Jesus' resurrection. As will now be shown, the conclusion which best fits the facts is that the literal resurrection of Jesus from the dead can be demonstrated to have occurred as a historical event. The following discussion in the last chapter is not dependent upon the work of these four scholars discussed here, but still arrives at a similar conclusion.

 


312

Chapter XIV. A Concluding Demonstration

It has been ascertained that the literal resurrection of Jesus from the dead is the historical event which best accounts for the known facts surrounding this occurrence. The objective in this chapter is to present one final demonstration by this writer that this event is the most probable. As explained earlier in this work, the word "demonstration" is used here not in the sense of "absolute proof", but rather as a reference to probabilities. Thus, it is asserted that the factual evidence is strong enough to warrant the conviction that the resurrection is the most probable for what occurred.

A. Historical Method

Modern historiography usually rules out the possibility of the miraculous a priori. According to this method, history is closed to the Supernatural workings of God in events such as miracles. In spite of the popularity of this procedure, it must be recognized that such a position is a historical presupposition.

This modern concept of history emerged from the intellectual environment beginning in the Enlightenment and continued on to nineteenth century historical Positivism. Miracles such as the resurrection were ruled out from the outset, often because of a supposed conflict with the concept of history. The result was an A priori rejection of all Supernatural intervention into history.[1]

One might wonder how historical this approach really is in   

 


313

actuality. In the case of a miracle-claim, the prevailing technique is to dismiss the possibility of it even before any investigation of the facts.

However, such was found to be an incorrect procedure in chapters two and three above. Science cannot rule out the miraculous a priori because the universe is no longer conceived of in terms of a closed system in which all events happen by means of a prescribed regularity. Science therefore cannot know beforehand that such miracles cannot occur. There can thus be no rejection of miracles such as the resurrection simply by referring to a modern world in which such Supernatural events do not occur.

In fact, modern science is quite limited as to what it can say about the resurrection. The scientific method is obviously concerned with measurable quantities. Concept such as peace, freedom or love cannot, of course, be measured in a test tube. Neither can a Geiger counter be used to verify the existence of Julius Caesar. In other words, empirical science has no instruments or other mean whereby past history can be investigated. In addition, history is nonrepeatable, which is also required in order for science to make a proper judgment. Therefore, all that can be ascertained via empirical science is that the resurrection cannot be negated because of the scientific world view. Rather, an impartial historical investigation of the facts is needed to see if this event actually occurred.

This is where the science of history emerges as the more proper method to be used in this instance. As math science, it was also shown that neither can history employ the scientific world view to rule out miracles a priori. We are thus faced once again with the  


314

need to historically investigate all of the facts to find the most probable solution. Modern historiography cannot negate the resurrection as a historical event without such an examination. It is clearly impossible (as shown in chapters two and three) to properly dismiss such a miracle-claim beforehand.

In this work, the historical method which is employed is therefore one which investigates the facts before a decision is made as to what can or did occur. The status of probability is given to the event which is the best explanation for the known facts. Such an inductive approach is actually more "scientific" in its endeavor to base the final conclusion upon a thorough historical investigation of what is known to have occurred.

B. The Historical Facts

Throughout this work, many references have been made to the known historical facts an how the resurrection is the best explanation for these events. What are these facts? What are the events and circumstances which are known to have happened in conjunction with the belief that Jesus rose from the dead?

Surrounding the resurrection event are many facts which are usually recognized as being historical by most scholars who deal with this subject. It is known that Jesus actually died[2] and that he was buried. Also historical is the fact that, after the death of their Master, the disciples were extremely depressed and disillusioned.   

 


315

For them, Jesus' ministry had been ended prematurely by the Roman cross. It is unanimously agreed that they were thus quite discouraged and downcast. Afterwards, as confounding as it was, the tomb in which Jesus was laid was later found to be empty.[3]

Very soon afterwards, history relates that the disciples had several experiences which they believed were appearances of the risen Jesus. After these experiences there was a drastic change in their disposition--a transformation which made them bold preachers even in the very cite where Jesus was crucified and buried. The result of this preaching was the birth of the Christian church, which began to meet on Sunday rather than on the Jewish Sabbath (Saturday). Lastly, it is an unquestionable historical fact that one of the most avid persecutors of the Christian church, Saul of Tarsus, was converted to Christianity by what he also believed was an appearance of the risen Jesus.[4]

From this summary, a minimum of ten historical facts can be gleaned which are held as being historical be the majority of theologians today. 1) Jesus actually died on the cross and 2) was buried in a tomb. 3) The disciples were extremely disillusioned and disconcerted by the death of Jesus, being bereft to all hope. 4) The same tomb in which Jesus was buried was found empty just a few days later, probably with the graveclothes still inside. 5) The disciples   

 


316

were the recipients of several experiences which they believed were resurrection appearances of Jesus. 6) Afterwards, the disciples experienced a complete transformation, being willing to die for their new faith. 7) The resultant preaching often took place in Jerusalem, the exact place where Jesus was killed and buried. 8) This preaching led to the birth of the church, 9) featuring Sunday as the most important day of worship, instead of Saturday. 10) Later, Paul was converted to Christianity by means of an experience which he also believed was an appearance of the risen Jesus.

These, then, are the historical facts which must be dealt with and explained. The gospels and New Testament as a whole agree with all ten of these either explicitly or implicitly. None of them is denied in any of the writings of the New Testament. In addition, as we have seen at various points in this work, the majority of theologians accept these as historical facts as well. It is therefore evident that the explanation which is given to the resurrection must also account for these events. The answer that is postulated in these early writings that Jesus literally rose from the dead. Any alternate explanation must explain all of these facts adequately and still cross the hardest hurdle by proposing a probable naturalistic theory for the appearances to the disciples. Thus, one who would deny the resurrection must both adequately explain all of these facts and offer a probable alternate view to the appearances. But as we have seen, no such probable alternative views exist, as even the more popular naturalistic theories fail to properly account for the facts which occurred.[5]

 


317

The enumerating of these facts also makes it evident that there are positive historical facts which support a belief in the resurrection as well. This event therefore does not only depend upon what Ladd refers to as "anti-criticism",[6] or the dismissal of all naturalistic theories which have been formulated against the resurrection. In other words, it is not only the evidence from the elimination of all alternate theories which makes the resurrection plausible, but there are actual "positive" facts which also demonstrate that this event is the most probable.

There are at least seven strong facts which indicate that Jesus actually rose from the dead. The first and by far the strongest fact is the positive New Testament claim that the disciples did indeed see the risen Jesus. There is not only the eyewitness testimony of Paul to the fact, but the gospels are at least close to and include the eyewitness testimony of the disciples (see Luke 1:1-4 as an example), as discussed above. Paul also records the extremely important fact that the original disciples were also preaching about the appearances of the risen Jesus to them (I Cor. 15:11-15).

The power of this New Testament testimony is twofold. First, no alternative theory is sufficient enough to explain these appearances and the subsequent conviction of their reality. But it is not only the rejection of these theories that makes this claim so important. Second, the known facts surrounding this event tend to corroborate   

 


318

it and make the claim highly credible. For instance, the disciples came to believe firmly in the resurrection despite their overwhelming disillusionment and disbelief. Thus, they came to believe in spite of themselves. Other facts are also left unexplained apart from the literal resurrection of Jesus.

Other events in addition to the actual appearances are also positive evidence for Jesus' resurrection. Second, the incredible change in the lives of the disciples from dejected men who fled at the arrest of Jesus to bold preachers who asserted the teachings of the life, death and resurrection of Jesus even in the face of their own death indicates unequivocally that these men firmly believed that Jesus had risen. Such elation is usually not the action of men who have been deceived by any kind of false, either. Such undoubting belief even to the point of dying for their faith is not the mark of men who had even the faintest misgivings about this event. The transformation of the disciples is best accounted for by actual appearances of the risen Jesus.

Third, the evidence of the empty tomb, while not in itself providing proof of the resurrection, is a positive point in favor of those who accept this event as historical. At the same time it requires a probable explanation by those who reject this event.[7] Even more on favor of the resurrection is the discovery of the gravesclothers inside the tomb, still unraveled with the body simply missing.


319

The attitude of the Jewish leaders in the book of acts reveals a fourth set of historical circumstances strongly in favor of Jesus' literal resurrection. When the disciples were confronted by the Jewish elders on various occasions in the early chapters of this book (see especially Acts 4-5), these followers of Jesus were not charged with spreading false tales about Jesus' resurrection. Neither did the Jews go to Jesus' tomb, reveal his body and so crush the central belief of Christianity.[8]

Fifth, the very birth of the Christian church depends upon the message of Jesus' resurrection. This event forms the very center of Christianity and of the earliest Christian message today apart from this event.[9]

A sixth fact pointing to the resurrection is the commemorating of this event in the Christian worship of Sunday instead of Saturday, the Jewish Sabbath. The first day of the week referred to as "the Lord's day" because Jesus was believe to have risen on a Sunday (see Rev. 1:10; cf. Jn. 20:19, 26). Early Jewish Christians apparently still gathered at the local synagogue for worship on Saturday, but for the Christian believer, Sunday was the day for such important practices as partaking of the Lord's supper (Acts 20:7) and   


320

the gathering of one's offspring (I Cor. 16:2). Soon Sunday became the day of pre-eminence for the Christians. But something must account for this day of worship since it was not the usual day. The New Testament witnesses that the change was due to Jesus' resurrection.

A seventh historical fact which makes the resurrection even more probable is the conversion of Paul. This enemy of the Christian church was suddenly converted to the faith which he had so avidly opposed. As Daniel Fuller shows, other naturalistic views which would account for this conversion are not convincing and must be rejected. Paul claimed his turnabout was due to an appearance of the risen Jesus and it is this view which still fits the facts best.[10]

These seven facts are therefore "positive" evidence for the resurrection of Jesus in addition to the "negative" evidence supplied by a refutation of the alternative views.[11] The appearances of the risen Jesus to his followers, the complete change in the disciples, the empty tomb, the attitude of the Jewish leaders in Acts, the existence of the church, the Christian worship day of Sunday and Paul's conversion are strong facts in favor of the resurrection. Earlier other historical evidence was also given, such as Daniel Fuller's thesis about the existence of the Gentile mission being dependent on the resurrection[12] and Paul Maier's presentation of  


321

both specific and circumstantial historical evidence for this event.[13]

However, contemporary theology has provided additional evidence for the resurrection which reinforces each of these other points of evidence. As explained in chapter one, the application of form criticism to the gospel records was thought to be helpful in ascertaining what the earliest church believed about Jesus. One of the main expectations was to uncover how the miraculous element was due to later additions and was not actually a part of the life of Jesus. But such was not to be the case.

Contrary to what may have been expected if the origin of everything miraculous in the New Testament was the faith of the early church rather than being a real part of Jesus' life, scholars cannot reach a form critical layer of tradition in which the resurrection belief is not present. In other words, form criticism has demonstrated that the resurrection belief is in the earliest strata of Christian belief. As Carl Braaten explains there results:

The form-critical study of the earliest Christian traditions has established beyond reasonable doubt that faith in the risen Christ is the point of departure and the essential content of the kerygma. Without the Easter faith there would have been no Christian church and the New Testament would not have been written. The belief that God raised Jesus from the dead on the third day is as old as the Christian faith and is now, as ever before, the article by which the church stands or falls…it may be refreshing to know that even the more skeptical historians agree that for primitive Christianity…the resurrection of Jesus from the dead was a real event in history, the very foundation of Jesus from the dead was a real event in history, the very foundation of faith, and not a mythical idea arising out of the creative imagination of believers.[14]


322

Other scholars likewise concur with Braaten in this view. Reginald Fuller agrees that there was no time in which the resurrection was not the center of Christian preaching.[15] Ramm asserts that the most important purpose served by form criticism has been to show that the miracles, and the resurrection in particular have been embedded in Christian belief from the very beginning.[16] Wand notes that the further back the texts are studied, the more clear it becomes that the risen Christ is the same as the Jesus of history.[17]

Thus form criticism only served to strengthen the belief that the resurrection is the historical basis of the Christian faith. It likewise confirmed the fact that this event occupied this very important position in theology since the very beginnings of Christianity.

In enumerating these historical facts surrounding the resurrection, it becomes apparent that this event is the best explanation for what as occurred. However, there is not only the evidence of these facts, but there is also the evidence from the refuted naturalistic theories. In addition, it was also found that there are at least seven major historical facts in favor of the resurrection besides those listed by such scholars as Maier and Daniel Fuller. These considerations therefore show that the literal resurrection of Jesus is the most probable conclusion to this historical question, especially when it is recognized that no alternate theories or other facts militate against this event.


323

C. The Theological Method

It becomes especially apparent from the material presented in this chapter (as well as in the rest of this work) that the pivotal point in this discussion if the experiences of the earliest followers of Jesus. All admit that these witnesses really believed that Jesus actually rose from the dead.[] But the focal point here concerns whether these experience were actually appearances of the risen Jesus.

Naturalistic theories of these experiences have been proposed ever since the earliest proclamation of these beliefs. Of the several alternative views which were refuted here, there were three major hypotheses. These were the swoon theory popularized by Heinrich Paulus, the subjective vision theory formulated by David Strauss and the legend or myth theory taught by Otto Pfleiderer and others.[]

It has been a very important emphasis in this work to provide a detailed and complete refutation of each of the naturalistic theories, especially these three major ones. Although it may be thought that the tendency was to "overkill" each of the theories by presenting more evidence than was necessary to dispose of them, it must be    

 


324p class="style7"> strenuously objected that such was the exact intention of this writer and for good reason. The need for a complete refutation of the alternative theories is too often overlooked in the works of those who also opt for the belief that the resurrection can be demonstrated. It is apparently not realized that the more thorough such a refutation is, the more probable the resurrection becomes.

TThe reason for this assertion is acute. There are several very important facts which point to the facticity of the resurrection, the main one being the appearances to the disciples. As long as a key alternate theory remains unrefuted (in whole or in part), these facts which point to the resurrection cannot be accorded the full impact which they warrant. But the more the alternate theories are refuted, the more outstanding the facts favoring the disciples' claims become, thus leaving the resurrection as still even more probable. Then it follows that the more completely such naturalistic theories are rejected, the higher the probability for the resurrection becomes as the facts which demonstrate the reality of this event are thereby shown to be valid. This is especially so when no other alternate theories are shown to be probable. Therefore we perceive the importance of complete refutations of three other views.

In examining the approaches of Pannenberg, Daniel Fuller, Ladd and Maier, it was found that each was not complete in his refutation of alternate views (to varying degrees). This is true in two different respects. First, many of the main reasons for rejecting each of the major theories were not presented. In other words, seldom was a theory rejected as thoroughly or strongly as it might have been.

Second, each of these scholars neglected completely (or almost so)   

 


325

one or more of the three major theories. In Pannenberg's section dealing with a defense of the resurrection against the alternate theories in his volume Jesus--God and Man, the swoon theory is neglected.[20] Fuller's treatise omits any specific refutation of Strauss' vision theory or of the legend or myth theory, although both are cited as alternate hypotheses. Also, the swoon theory is quickly passed over with very little disproof.[21] Ladd also ignores the legend or myth theory in his treatment of the naturalistic theories,[22] as does Maier.[23] Although it has been ascertained that these scholars were generally successful in their overall treatments of the resurrection one cannot help but think that since it was their desire to demonstrate the probability of the resurrection, a more complete refutation would have been desirable.

Since a more adequate refutation of the alternate theories makes the resurrection more probable, the treatment of the three major theories and several lesser ones in this work has endeavored to be complete. In fact, the desire was especially to present more evidence than was necessary in order to dismiss each one. The New Testament states that Jesus rose from the dead and demonstrated this by appearing to his followers. Other facts also corroborate this event. With these    

 


326

naturalistic theories thus shown to be quite inadequate to properly explain what occurred, the facts for the resurrection are shown to be highly probable. If one believes that it is still difficult to formulate an alternative view which logically, historically and theologically accounts for the known facts. The resurrection is the highly probable historical fact which best accounts for what occurred.

D. Convinced by the Facts

One interesting point with regard to the facts of the resurrection is that after an examination of the evidence, many scholars who had once rejected this event came to believe that it could be demonstrated to have occurred. They were convinced by the weight of the facts that this event was historical. This is not to say that no one who had been taught that the resurrection occurred has ever rejected such information later. But this writer knows of no instance where the resurrection was rejected after an examination of the facts, as was the case with these who accepted the reality of this event after just such an examination, against their former views.

Frank Morison, a lawyer, is surely one of the best examples of a scholar who became convinced against his earlier convictions after studying the evidence for the resurrection. As a young man, Morison began a serious study of the life of Jesus, being much influenced by the works of German liberal scholarship. He did not accept the miracles   

 


327

in Jesus' life and was determined to remove what he felt were mythical outgrowths.

Ten years after his first studies he received the opportunity to study the life of Jesus in depth. An examination of the last week of Jesus' like in particular brought him to a study of the resurrection. However, in endeavoring to write a book exposing these myths which he thought he would find, he was compelled by the factual evidence to write quite a different book in favor of the resurrection. This work, entitled Who Moved the Stone?, became a defense of the resurrection against the theological views formerly held by Morison himself. He explains that it was because of his investigation of the facts that he reversed his former views and that caused him to realize not only that the resurrection occurred, but that it could be demonstrated.[24]

The late Simon Greenleaf, past Harvard professor of law and one of the greatest legal minds that America has ever produced, was a religious skeptic. Challenge by his students to apply the techniques of his legal masterpiece A Treatise on the Law of Evidence to the resurrection of Jesus, Greenleaf became a believer. He later wrote a book, the long title of which is An Examination of the Testimony of the Four Evangelists by the Rules of Evidence Administered in the Courts of Justice.[25] In this work he defends the resurrection and

 


328

explains how, when judged by the laws of legal evidence, the event can be demonstrated to have actually occurred.[26]

Another scholar who was convinced by an examination of the evidence is medial doctor Viggo Olsen. He described himself as an agnostic who did not believe in the Supernatural elements of Christianity. But more than this, he constantly questioned the Christian faith and attempted to disprove it. Through the process of trying to expose these beliefs, he studied the resurrection and other evidences. Later he became convinced that God did exist and that there was more than a sufficient amount of demonstration for the resurrection. He realized that this event actually occurred and that as such it was the center of the Christian faith. It is noteworthy that Simon Greenleaf's book on the Christian evidences was a key influence on Olsen.[27]

Other scholars who have looked impartially at the facts have often likewise concluded that the evidence for the resurrection establishes it as a historical event. For instances, such was the conclusion of lawyer Sir Edward Clarke, K.C, who also investigated the resurrection in terms of the evidential aspect. He remarked that this factual support was conclusive, as he had often secured a positive verdict in courts of law with less evidence.[25] McDowell lists numerous

 


329

other instances where other scholars came to similar conclusions after an impartial examination of the facts.[29]

When speaking of such examples, the New Testament instances of similar results should not be ignored. It is known, for instance, that Jesus' brother James was almost assuredly not a believer before the resurrection (Jn, 7:5; cf. Mk. 3:21, 31-34). But after an appearance from Jesus he became a Christian and the leader of the Jerusalem church (I Cor. 15:7; cf. Gal. 2:1-10). The example of Paul changing from a persecutor of the church (Acts 7:57-59; 9:1-2) to an ardent follower of Christ has already been mentioned above (see I Cor. 15:8-9). Again it was an appearance of the risen Jesus that caused this change of heart. It is the opinion of contemporary theological scholarship that both of these men became Christians in spite of their former beliefs because of an appearance of the risen Lord.[30]

This brief presentation has shown that many have accepted the resurrection as a historical event after a careful investigation of the data, even when formerly opposed to this belief. Also extremely interesting is the stance taken by two "God-is-dead" or secular theologians, William Hamilton and John A.T. Robinson. In spite of the secular theological positions of these two men, they also recognize the strong evidence for the resurrection.

For Hamilton, the resurrection and empty tomb are highly probable. In fact, he believes that the resurrection may be affirmed   

 


330

as a regular historical event.[31] Robinson admits that the empty tomb is very difficult to dismiss because of the good evidence for this event.[32]

This survey of several scholars was present in order to show how strong the evidence for the resurrection is for the one who looks impartically at the facts. Several scholars who were once opposed to this belief were convinced otherwise after an investigation of the evidence, as were others who studied the data in favor of this event. The New Testament also records two examples of men who were convinced by resurrection appearances of Jesus against their former views. Even two secular theologians were able to grant a high credibility to the resurrection, as one accepted it as a historical event while the other admitted that it would be hard to reject the strong evidence in favor of it.

Such is the convincing evidence for the resurrection of Jesus Christ. As church historian Wand reminds is about this event:

All the strictly historical evidence we have is in favor of it, and those scholars who reject it ought to recognize that they do so on some other ground than that of scientific history.[33]

This serves as a good reminder about our earlier conclusion to accept the answer to the question of the resurrection which best fits the facts. Wand note that if naturalistic theories are unable to account for an event which claims that a miracle has taken place, that a Supernatural alternative must not be viewed as impossible. It is unscientific to begin with the presupposition that miraculous   

 


331

event cannot occur. Rather, a critical historian can only examine the facts involved in the situation before him and decide on the basis of this evidence. It the probable event is a Supernatural one, then it must be accepted as such, as with the resurrection. Modern science and history cannot refute this event, as we have seen.[34]

Therefore, in accordance with this historical principle, the literal resurrection of Jesus Christ from the dead must be accepted as an actual historical event according to its high degree of plausibility. Once again, those who find it difficult to accept this conclusion will have an even more difficult time endeavoring to formulate an alternative theory which is historically probable. It is not only possible to completely refute all of the naturalistic alternate theories which oppose a literal resurrection, as shown above, but there are several important facts in favor of this event. The most important of these facts is that, in all probability, Jesus appeared empirically to his followers after his death on the cross and no other thesis apart from the literal resurrection is capable of properly explaining these appearances. The resurrection of Jesus is thereby highly probable.

E. The Center of Christianity

It must be concluded that the knowledge that Jesus' resurrection is a historical fact is one of the ultimate importance to the Christian faith. As was shown in chapter eleven, one cannot hold that Jesus is dead and that he never rose from the tomb and still hold that   


332

Jesus is alive today in any unique sense. Neither can one hold that such doctrines as Christology and subsequent beliefs concerning salvation can have the same validity if the one around when such beliefs revolve is dead, not even being able to conquer death himself. If such were the case, there would thus be no reason to suspect that Christians will receive such blessings either. As Paul asserts, apart from the resurrection there is no Christian faith at all (I Cor. 15:12-19). For this reason, the reality of the resurrection is absolutely essential for Christian faith.[35]

Therefore, the conclusion which asserts that Jesus actually rose from the dead is no meaningless assertion. It is not a matter of simply affirming the resurrection. To the contrary, it is very important to accept this event as historical, for in so doing the remainder of the Christian faith is demonstrated to be valid.

This is also why it was asserted earlier that the concept of faith as defined by Kierkegaard and Barth could remain valid in spite of the critiques of these two theologians. Each of these scholars agrees with the New Testament in recognizing that every individual man is a sinner in need of repentance, or a total change in one's life. A total surrender to God in faith, trusting Jesus' substitutionary death on the cross to forgive these sins, is needed for salvation. The result is a total change in one's life, a total commitment based upon the death of Jesus. In these principles,   


333

Kierkegaard and Barth both follow the New Testament definition of salvation. Jesus claimed to have some to this world chiefly to die a substitutionary death in order to procure such salvation for those who commit their lives in faith to God through Him Son (see Mark 10:45; John 1:12-13; I Cor. 15:1-4).

Such teachings are often ignored today as outmoded an due to ancient superstitions. But in light of out conclusions concerning Jesus' resurrection, such tendencies to dismiss the New Testament teaching on salvation are unwarranted. Since the resurrection is accepted as a Supernatural event, as shown here, then Jesus' ministry to mankind was for a reason. It would be illogical to accept the Supernatural demonstration of Jesus' mission and then reject the message which is corroborated by it. As the resurrection event cannot be denied neither can the resurrection message of the subsequent availability of this salvation.

 

...> To End Notes


334

 

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Anderson, Charles C. Critical Quests of Jesus. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1969.

______.The Historical Jesus: A Continuing Quest. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1972

Anderson, J.N.D. Christianity and Comparative Religion. Downers Grove: Inter Varsity Press 1974.

______.Christianity: The Witness of History. London: Tyndale Press, 1969.

Barclay, William. The Mind of Jesus. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1961.

Barnes, Wesley. The Philosophy and Literature of Existentialism. Woodbury: Barron's Educational Series, 1968.

Barth, Karl. Anselm: Fides Quarens Intellectum. Translated by Ian W. Robertson. Richmond: John Knox Press, 1960.

______. Dogmatics in Outline. Translated by G.T. Thompson. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1959

______.How I Changed My Mind. Richmond: John Knox Press, 1966.

______.The Doctrine of Reconciliation. Volume IV, Part One of Church Dogmatic. Edited by G.W. Bromily and T.F. Torrence. Thirteen Volumes. Edinburgh: T. and T. Clark, 1961.

______.The Faith of the Church. Edited by Jean-Louis Leuba. Translated by Gariel Vahanian. New York: Meridian Books, Inc., 1958.

______.Theology and Church: Shorter Writings 1920-1928. Translated by Louise Pettibone Smith. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962.

______.The Resurrection of the Dead. Translated by H.J. Stenning. New York: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1933.

______.The Word of God and the Word of Man. Translated by Douglas Horton. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1957.

Barth, Markus, and Fletcher, Verne H. Acquittal by Resurrection. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1964.

Becker, Carl L. The Heavenly City of te Eighteenth-Century Philosophers. . New Haven: Yale University Press, 1969.

Benoit, Pierre. Jesus and the Gospel. Translated by Renet Weatherhead. New York: The Seabury Press, 1973.

______, and Murphy, Roland. Immorality and Resurrection. New York: Herder and Herder, 1970.

Berger, Peter L. A Rumor of Angels. Garden City: Doubleday and Company, Inc., 1969.

Blaikie, Robert J. "Secular Christianity" and God Who Acts. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1970.

Bluh, Otto and Elder, Joseph Dension. Principles and Applications of Physics. New York: Interscience Publishers, Inc., 1955.

BonHoeffer, Dietrich. Christ the Center. Translated by John Bowden. New York: Harper and Row Publishers 1966.

Boring, Edwin G.; Langfield, Herbert S.; and Weld, Harry P., Editors. Foundations of Psychology. New York. Harper and Row, Publishers, 1960.

Bornkamm, Gunther. Jesus of Nazareth Translated by Irene and Fraser McLuskey with James M. Robinson. New York. Harper and Row, Publishers, 1960.

Braaten, Carl. History and Hermeneutics. Volume II of New Directions in Theology Today. Edited by William Hordern. Seven volumes. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1966.

Bronowski, J. and Mazlish, Bruce. The Western Intellectial Tradition. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962. p>

Brown, Delwin; James, Ralph E.; and Reeves, Gene, Editors. Process Philosophy and Christian Thought. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1971.

Brown, James. Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Buber and Barth. New York Collier Books, 1967.

Brown, Raymond E. New Testament Essays. Milwaukee: The Bruce Publishing Company, 1965.

______.The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus. New York: Paulist Press, 1973.

Bruce, F.F. Jesus and Christian Origins Outside the New Testament. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1974.

______.The New Testament Documents: Are They Reliable? Fifth revised edition. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1967.

Brunner, Emil. The Christian Doctrine of Creation and Redemption. Volume II of Dogmatics. Translated by Olive Wyon. Three volumes. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1952. ______.The Mediator. Translated by Olive Wyon. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1947.

Bulfinch, Thomas. The Age of Fable. Greenwich: Fawcett Publications, Inc., 1961.

Bultmann, Rudolf. History and Eschatology. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962.

______.Jesus Christ and Mythology. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1958.

______.Theology of the New Testament. Two volumes in one. Translated by Kendrick Grobel. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1951.

Burtt, Ewin A. Types of Religious Philosophy. Revised edition. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1939.

Cassels, Louis. Christian Primer. Garden City: Doubleday and Company, Inc., 1967.

______.This Fellow Jesus. New York: Pyramid Publications, 1973.

Cassirer, Ernst. Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics. Translated by O. Theodor Benfrey. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1956.

Clough, Shepard B.; Garsoian, Nina G.; and Hicks, David L. Ancient and Medieval. Volume one of A History of the Ancient World. Three volumes. Boston: D.C. Heath and Company, 1967.

Cullmann, Oscar; Wolfson, Harry A.; Jaeger, Werner; and Cadbury, Henry J. Immortality and the Resurrection. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1965.

Cutten, George Barton. Speaking with Tongues Historically and Psychologically Examined. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1927.

Dobson, C.C. The Empty Tomb and the Rise Lord. Second edition revised. London and Edinburgh: Marshall, Morgan and Scott, Ltd., no date.

Dray, William H., Editor. Philosophical Analysis and History. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966.

Earle, Edward M., Editor. Makers of Modern Strategy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1943.

Eliade, Mircea. Mephistopheles and the Androgyne: Studies in Religious Myth and Symbol. Translated by J.M. Cohen. New York: Sheed and Ward, 1965.

______.Myth and Reality. Translated by William R. Task. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1963.

______.The Quest: History and Meaning in Religion. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1969.

Evans, C.F. Resurrection and the New Testament. Volume 12 of Studies in Biblical Theology, Second Series. Naperville: Alec R. Allenson, Inc., 1970.

Finley, M.I. The World of Odysseus. New York: The Viking Press, 1954.

Fuller, Daniel P. Easter Faith and History. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1965.

Fuller, Reginald. The Formation of the Resurrection Narratives. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1971.

Gaebelein, Frank E., Editor. Christianity Today. Westwood: Fleming E. Revell Company, 1968.

Gilson, Etienne. Reason and Revelation in the Middle Ages. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1966.

Grant, Robert M. A Historical Introduction to the New Testament. London: Collins, 1963.

______.Miracle and Natural Law. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company, 1952.

Hamilton, William. The Modern Reader's Guide to John. New York: Association Press, 1959.

______.The New Essence of Christianity. New York: Association Press, 1961.

Harnack, Adolf. What is Christianity? Translated by Thomas Bailey Saunders. Third and revised edition. London: Gerald Duckworth and Company, Ltd., 1964.

Hartwell, Herbert. The Theology of Karl Barth. London: Gerald Duckworth and Company, Ltd., 1964.

Heick, O.W. History of Protestant Theology. Volume two of A History of Christian Thought. By J.L. Neve. Two volumes. Philadelphia: The Muhlenberg Press, 1946.

Henry, Carl F.H., Editor. Jesus of Nazareth: Saviour and Lord. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1966.

Hooke, S.H. Middle Eastern Mythology. Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1966.

Hordern, William. A Layman's Guide to Protestant Theology. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1956.

______.Introduction. Volume I of New Direction in Theology Today. Edited by William Hordern. Seven volumes. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1966.

Hume, David. An Abstract of a Treatise of Human Nature. Cambridge: The University Press, 1964.

______.A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1964.

______.Essays, Literary, Moral of David Hume. London: Ward, Lock and Bowden, Ltd., no date.

______.The Essential Works of David Hume. Edited by Ralph Cohen. New York: Bantam Books, Inc., 1965.

______.The History of England. Six volumes. London: Gilberg and Revington, Printers, 1849.

Hunter, Archibald M. Introducting the New Testament. Second edition. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1957.

James, William. The Principles of Psychology. Two Volumes. New York: Dover Publishing House, 1966.

Jauncey, James. Science Returns to God. Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1966.

Johnson, Howard A. and Thulstrup, Niels, Editors. A Kierkegaard Critique. Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1962.

Kant, Immanuel. Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone. Translated by Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt H. Hudson. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1960.

Kaufman, Gordon. Systematic Theology: A Historicist Perspective. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1968.

Kierkegaard, Soren. Attack Upon "Christendom". Translated by Walter Lowrie. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1972.

______.Concluding Unscientific Postscript. Translated by David Swenson. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974.

______.Philosophical Fragments. Translated by David Swenson. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974.

______.The Point of View for My Work as an Author. Edited by Benjamin Nelson. Translated by Walter Lowrie. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962.

King, Marie Gentert, Editor. Foxe's Book of Mertyrs. Westwood: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1968.

Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Volume II, Number 2 of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Edited by Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap and Charles Martin Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1971.

Ladd, George Eldon. I Believe in the Resurrection of Jesus. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1975.

Lessing, Gotthold E. Lessing's Theological Writings. Edited by Henry Chadwick. London: Adam and Charles Black Ltd., 1956.

Lewis, C.S. God in the Dock. Edited by Walter Hooper. Grand Rapids: William E. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1973.

______.Miracles. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1965.

Lightfoot, J.B., Editor and Translator. The Apostolic Fathers Grand Rapids Baker Book House, 1971.

Locke, John. The Reasonableness of Christianity. Edited by I.T. Ramesy. Standford: Stanford University Press, 1958.

Machen J. Gresham. Christianity and liberalism. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1923.

Macquarrie, John. An Existentialist Theology. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1965.

Maier, Paul L. First Easter. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1973.

Marty, Martin C. and Peerman, Dean G. A Handbook of Christian Theologians. Cleveland: World Publishing Company, 1965.

Marxsen, Willi. The Resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth. Translated by Margret Kohl. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970.

Mazlish, Bruce. The Riddle of History: The Great Speculators from Vico to Freud. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966.

McDowell, Josh. Evidence that Demands a Verdict. San Bernadino: Published by Campus Crusade for Christ International, no date.

McKelway, Alexander J. The Systematic Theology of Paul Tillich. New York: Dell Publishing Company, Inc, 1964.

McLeman, James. Resurrection Then and Now. Philadelphia and New York: J.B. Lippincott Company, 1967.

McNaugher, John. Jesus Christ the Same Yesterday, Today and Forever. New York: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1947.

Meeks, M. Douglas. Origins of the Theology of Hope. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1974.

Miller, Laurence. Jesus Christ is Alive. Boston: W.A. Wilde Company, 1949.

Moltmann, Jurgen. Religion, Revolution and the Future. Translated by M. Douglas Meeks. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1969.

______.Theology of Hope Transalted by James W. Leitch. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1967.

Montgomery, John Warwick. History and Christianity. Downers Grove: Inter Varsity Press, 1972.

______.The Shape of the Past: An Introduction to Philosophical Historiography. Ann Arbor: Edwards Brothers, Inc., 1962.

______.The Suicide of Christian Theology. Minneapolis: Bethany Fellowship, Inc., 1970.

______.Where is History Going? Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1969.

______, and Altizer, Thomas J.J. The Altizer-Montgomery Dialogue. Chicago: Inter Varsity Press, 1967.

Moore, W. Edgar. Creative and Critical Thinking. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1967.

Morison, Frank. Who Moved the Stone? London: Faber and Faber Ltd., 1962.

Morris, Henry. Many Infallible Proofs. San Diego: Creation-Life Publishers, 1974.

Morris, William, Editor. The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. New York: American Heritage Publishing Company, Inc. and the Houghton Mifflin Company, 1970.

Mowinckel, Sigmund. The Old Testament as Word of God. Translated by Reidar B. Bjornard. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1959.

Ogden, Schubert M. Christ Without Myth. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers 1961.

______.The Reality of God and other Essays. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966.

Orr, James. The Resurrection of Jesus. Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1965.

Pamphilus, Eusebuis. Ecclesiastical History. Translated by Christian Frederick Cruse. Grand Rapids: Baker Book House, 1969.

Pannenberg, Wolfhart. Basic Questions in Theology. Translated by George H. Kehm. Two volumes. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1972.

______.Jesus-God and Man. Translated by Lewis L. Wilkens and Duane A. Priebe. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1968.

______. Editor. Revelation as History. Translated by David Granskou. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1968.

_______.Theology and the Kindgom of God. Edited by Richard John Neuhaus. Philadephia: The Westminster Press, 1969.

Perkins, Robert L. Soren Kierkegaard. Richmond: John Knox Press, 1969.

Perrin, Norman. What is Redaction Criticism? Edited by Daniel O. Via. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1971.

Pfleiderer, Otto. Philosophy and Development of Religion. Two volumes. Edinburgh: William Blackwood and Sons, 1894.

______.Primitive Christianity. Translated by W. Montgomery. Four volumes. Clifton: Reference Book Publishers, 1965.

______.The Early Christian Conception of Christ. London: Williams and Norgate, 1905.

Ramm, Bernard. A Handbook of Contemporary Theology. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1966.

______.Protestant Christian Evidences. Chicago: Moody Press, 1953.

Ramsey, A.M. The Resurrection of Christ. Second edition. London and Glascow: Collins, 1965.

Randall, John Herman, Jr. The Making of the Modern Mind. Revised edition. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1940.

Renan, Ernst. Life of Jesus. Volume I of the The History of the Origins of Christianity. No translator given. London: Mathieson and Company, no date. Revised Standard Version of the Bible. New York: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1946, 1952.

Ricoeur, Paul. History and Truth. Translated by Charles A. Kelbley. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1965.

Robertson, Archibald T. Word Pictures in the New Testament. Six volumes. Nashville: Broadman Press, 1931.

Robinson, John A.T. Exploration Into God. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1967.

______.Honest to God. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1963.

Runes, Dagobert, Editor. Dictionary of Philosophy. Totowa Littlefield, Adams and Company, 1967.

Santoni, Ronald, Editor. Religious Language and the Problem of Relgious Knowledge. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1968.

Schaaffs, Werner. Theology, Physics and Miracles. Translated by Richard L. Renfield. Washington, D.C.: Canon Press, 1974.

Schaeffer, Francis. Escape from Reason. Downers Grove: Inter Varsity Press, 1968.

______.The Church Before the Watching World. Downers Grove: Inter Varsity Press, 1971

______.The God Who is There. Downers Grove: Inter Varsity Press, 1968.

Schleiermacher, Friedrich. On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers. Translated by John Oman. New York: Harper and Brothers, Publishers, 1958.

______.The Christian Faith. Edited by H.R. Mackintosh and J.S. Stewart. Two volumes. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1963.

Schonfield, Hug. The Passover Plot. New York: Bantam Books, Inc., 1967.

Schweitzer, Albert. The Quest of the Historical Jesus. Translated by W. Montgomery. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1971.

Shestov, Lev. Athens and Jersusalem. Translated by Bernard Martin. No city: Ohio University Press, 1966.

Smith, Wilbur M. The Supernaturalness of Christ. Boston: M.A. Wilde Company, 1954.

Sparrow-Simpson, W.J. The Resurrection and the Christian Faith. Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1965.

Spinoza, Benedict. The Chief Works of Benedict de Spinoza. Translated by R.H.M. Elves. Two volumes. New York: Dover Pubications, Inc., 1951.

Stagg, Frank; Hinton, E. Glenn; and Oates, Wayne E. GLossolalia: Tongue Speaking in Biblical, Historical, and Psyhoclogical Perspective. Nashville: Abingdon Press 1967.

Stone, Ronald J. Reinhold Niebuhr: Prophet to Politicians. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1972. Stott, John R.W. Basic Christianity. Chicago: Inter-Varsity Press, 1965.

______.Your Mind Matters: The Place of the Mind in the Christian Life. Downers Grove: Inter Varsity Press, 1973.

Strauss, David Friedrich. A New Life of Jesus. No translator given. Second edition. Two volumes. London: Williams and Norgate, 1879.

______.The Old Faith and the New. Translated by Mathilde Blind. Two volumes. New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1874.

Swinburne, Richard. The Concept of Miracle. London: The macmillan Company and St. Martin's Press, 1970.

Tenney, Merrill C. The Reality of the Resurrection. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1963.

Thomas, Owen C., Editor. Attitudes Toward Other Religions. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1969.

Throckmorton, Burton H. The New Testament and Mythology. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1959.

Tillich, Paul. Systematic Theology. Three volumes. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1971.

Tomlin, E.W.F. The Western Philosophers. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1967.

Urs von Balthasar, Hans. The Theology of Karl Barth. Translated by John Drury. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1971.

Van Buren, Paul M. The Secular Meaning of the Gospel. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1963.

Vine, W.E. An Expository Dictionary of New Testament Words. New York: Harper and Brothers, Publishers, 1960.

Walsh, W.H. Philosophy of History. New York: Harper and Brothers, Publishers, 1960.

Wand, William. Christianity: A Historical Religion? Valley Forge: Judson Press, 1972.

Weiss, Johannes. Earliest Christianity: A History of the Period A.D. 30-150. Edited by Frederick C. Grant. Two volumes. Magnolia: Peter Smith, Publishers, 1959.

Wells, H.G. The Outline of History. Two volumes. Garden City: Garden City Books, 1949.

 


344

Articles, Booklets and Essays

Anderson, J.N.D. The Evidence for the Resurrection. Downers Grove Inter Varsity Press, 1966.

Berlin, Sir Isaac. "The Concept of Scientific History". Philosophical Analysis and History. Edited by William H. Dray. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966.

Brauch, Manfred. "Head and Heart Go to Seminary". Christianity Today. Volume XIX, Number 19. June 20, 1975, pages 11-12.

Brown, Raymond E. "The Resurrection and Biblical Criticism". Commonweal. November 24, 1967, pages 32-36.

Bultmann, Rudolf. "New Testament and Mythology". Kerygma and Myth. Edited by Hans Werner Bartsch. Translated by Reginald H. Fuller. New York: Harper and Row Publishers, 1961. ______."Study of the Synoptic Gospels". Form Criticism. Translated by Frederick C. Grant. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962.

Chamberlain, Nelson R. "Jurgen Moltmann: Apostle of Christian Hope?" Christian Today. Volume XVIII, Number 19. June 21, 1974, pages 6-10.

Clark, Gordan B. "Bultmann's Three-Storied Universe". Christianity Today. Edited by Frank Gaebelein. Westwood: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1968.

Collins, James. "Faith and Reflection in Kierkegaard". A Kierkegaard Critque. Edited by Howard A. Johnson and Niels Thulstrup. Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1962.

Dobson, Daniel. "What is 'Myth'?" The Age of Fable. By Thomas Bulfinch. Greenwich: Fawcett Publications, Inc., 1961.

Feibleman, James K. "Myth". Dictionary of Philosophy. Edited by Dagobert Runes. Totowa: Littlefield, Adams and Company, 1967.

Farm, Vergilius. "Deim". Dictionary of Philosophy. Edited by Dagobert Runes. Totowa: Littlefield, Adams and Company, 1967.

Fey, Harold E. "Apocalypse at Easter". Christian Century. Volume XC, Number 16. April 18, 1973, pages 453-454.

Gardiner, Patrick. "The Philosophy of History". Volume 6 of The International Encyclopedia of Social Science. Edited by David L. Sills. No city: The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, 1968.

Gilmour, S. MacLean. "Luke--Introduction". Volume 8 of The Interpreter's Bible. Edited by George Arthur Buttrick. Twelve volumes. Nashville: Abingdon-Cokesbury Press, 1951-1956.

Hamilton, Peter N. "Some Proposals for a Modern Christology". Process Philosophy and Christian Thought. Edited by Delwin Brown, Ralph E. James, Jr. and Gene Reeves. Inianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1971.

Heinecken, Martin J. "Soren Kierkegaard". A Handbook of Christian Theologians. Edited by Martin C. Marty and Dean G. Peerman. Cleveland: The World Publishing Company, 1965.

Kick, John. "Theology and Verification". Religious Language and the Problem of Religious Knowledge. Edited by Ronald E. Santoni. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1968.

Howard, Wilbert F. "John--Introduction". Volume 8 of The Interpreter's Bible. Edited by George Arthur Buttrick. Tweleve volumes. Nashville: Abingdon-Cokesbury Press, 1951-1956.

Hudson, R. Lofton. "What One Easter Meant to Me". Christian Century. Volume XC, Number 16. April 18, 1973, pages 450-451.

Johnson, William Hallock. "The Keystone of the Arch". Theology Today. Edited by John A. MacKay. Volume VI, Number 1. April, 1949 January, 1950, pages 12-24.

Johnson, Sheman E. "Matthew--Introduction". Volume 7 of The Interpreter's Bible. Edited by George Arthur Buttrick. Twelve volumes. Nashville: Abingdon-Cokesbury Press, 1951-1956.

Knapp, James F. "Myth in the Powerhouse of Change". Volume XX, Number 1. The Centennial Review. Winter, 1976, pages 56-74.

Loomer, Bernard M. "Christian Faith and Process Philosophy". Proces Philosophy and Christian Thought. Edited by Delwin Brown, Ralph E. James, Jr. and Gene Reeves. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1971.

Maier, Paul L. "The Empty Tomb as History". Christianity Today. Volume XIX, Number 13. March 28, 1975, pages 4-6.

______."Who Was Responsible for the Trial and Death of Jesus?" Christian Today. Volume XVIII, Number 14. April 12, 1974, page 8-11.

Martin, Lawrence E. "The Risen Christ". The Christian Century. Volume XC, Number 20. May 16, 1973, page 577.

McDermott, Brian O., S.J. "Pannenberg's Resurrection Christology: A Critique". Theological Studies. Volume 35, Number 4. December, 1974, pages 711- 721.

Nagel, Ernest. "Determinisim in History". Philosophical Analysis and History. Edited by William H. Dray. New York: Harper an Row, Publishers, 1966.

Ogden, Schubert. "Toward a New Thesim". Process Philosophy and Christian Thought. Edited by Delwin Brown, Ralph E. James, Jr. and Gene Reeves. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1971.

Olsen, Viggo. The Agnostic Who Dared to Search. Chicago: Moody Press, 1974.

Pinnock, Clark. "On the Third Day". Jesus of Nazareth Saviour and Lord. Edited by Carl F.H. Henry. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman's Publishing Company, 1966.

Rendtorff, Rolf. "The Concept of Revelation in Ancient Isreal". Revelation as History. Edited by Wolfhart Pannenberg. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1968.

Smith, Robert W. "Should the Christian Argue?" Christianity Today. Volume XVIII, Number 10. February 15, 1974, pages 14-18.

Steiger, Lothar. "Revelation-History and Theological Reason: Critiqiue of the Theology of Wolfhart Pannenberg". History and Hermeneutic. Volume IV of Journal for Theology and the Church. Edited by Robert W. Funk and Gerhard Ebeling. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, Inc., 1967.

Turner, Victor. "Myth and Symbol". Volume 10 of The International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. Edited by David Sills. No city: The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, 1968.

VanderMolen, Ronald. "'Where is History Going?' and Historical Scholarship: A Response". Fides et Historia. Volume V, Nos. 1-2. Fall, 1972 and Spring, 1973, pages 109-112.

Wright, G. Ernest. "The Book of Numbers". Volume 2 of The New Interpreter's Bible. Edited by George Arthur Buttrick. Twelve volumes. Nashville: Abingdon- Cokesbury Press, 1951-1956.

Yamauchi, Edwin M. "Easter--Myth, Happuscination or History?" Christian Today.. Volume XVIII, Number 12. March 15, 1974, pages 4-7 and Volume XVIII, Number 12. March 29, 1974, pages 12-16.


347

 

INDEX OF PERSONS

(Important References)

Anderson, Charles C., 5-6, 8, 125, 129, 146, 248

Anderson, J.N.D., 13, 165, 276

Barclay, William, 154

Barnes, Wesley, 178

Barth, Karl, 114, 127, 198-218, 221-224, 271, 300-306

Barth, Markus, 7, 8

Becker, Carl L., 13, 222

Berger, Peter L., 49-50, 85

Bishop, Jim, 124

Blaikie, Robert J., 252, 272, 301, 312

Bonhoeffer, Dietrich, 219

Bornkamm, Gunther, 4, 5, 11, 219-220

Braaten, Carl, 321

Brauch, Manfred, 60, 76

Bronowski, J., 39, 49-50, 107

Brown, Raymond E., 133, 145, 155, 159

Bruce, F.F., 276

Brunner, Emil, 218-219

Bultmann, Rudolf, 8, 10-11, 26-27, 31-32, 35, 117, 136, 149-152, 160, 168-171, 173, 215-216, 217, 288, 293-294, 323

Burtt, Edwin A., 57, 93, 96, 114

Cassels, Louis, 13

Cassirer, Ernst, 47

Clark, Gordon H., 37, 39, 47-48

Clough, Shepard B., 14, 49-50

Conzelmann, Hans, 11

Cutten, George B., 59

Dobson, C.C., 6

Dodson, Daniel, 29

Eliade, Mircea, 30, 32

Feibleman, James K., 30

Ferm, Vergilius, 84

Finley, M.I., 59

Fletcher, Verne H., 8

Fuller, Daniel P., 6, 55, 201, 220, 225, 244, 252, 260-267, 272-273 307ff., 320, 324-325

Fuller, Reginald, 8, 9, 12, 155, 156, 216, 322

Gardiner, Patrick, 49, 51

Garsoian, Nina G., 14, 49-50

Gilson, Etienne, 60-61

Grant, Robert M., 143, 158-159

Grass, Hans, 20

Greenleaf, Simon, 327-328

Hamilton, Peter, 21-23

Hamilton, William, 159, 330, 332

Harnack, Adolf, 117, 288

Hartwell, Herbert, 199

Heick, O.W., 39, 83-85

Heinecken, Martin J., 174, 176, 189, 197

Henry, Carl F.H., 203, 214

Hick, John 18-20

Hicks, David L., 14, 49-50

Hooke, S.H., 31, 33, 34

Hordern, William, 112, 114

Hudson, R. Lofton, 294

Hume, David, 27, 39, 82-113, 289-290

Hunter, Archibald M., 158-159

Ignatius, 143

Jauncey, James, 36, 37, 39, 41

Johnson, William H., 255

Josephus, Flavius, 275-276

Kant, Immanuel, 183

Kaufman, Gordon, 136, 141

Keim, Karl T., 131

Kierkegaard, Soren, 172-197, 207, 300-306

Knapp, James F., 30

Kuhn, Thomas S., 36, 37, 38

Ladd, George E., 132, 244, 267-274, 295-296, 297, 307ff., 324-325

Lessing, Gotthold E., 181-183

Lewis, C.S., 13, 27-28, 90, 91, 92, 97, 109, 163, 272-273

Locke, John, 84

Loomer, Bernard, 21

Machen, J. Gresham, 290, 297

Macquattie, John, 31

Maier, Paul, 14-15, 17, 58, 123, 125, 129, 274-285, 307ff., 312, 324-325

Martin, Lawrence E., 284

Marxsen, Willi, 4, 5, 7, 8, 9, 11, 12, 217, 294-295

Mazish, Bruce, 39, 49-50, 107

McDerott, Brian C., 229, 249

McDowell, Josh, 328, 329

McKelway, Alexander J., 129

McLeman, James, 8, 145

McNaugher, John, 28, 44, 82, 91, 95, 96, 225

Meeks, M. Douglas, 226

Miller, Laurence, 4

Moltmann, Jurgen, 220-221

Montgomery, John W., 16-17, 37, 43, 44, 52f., 59, 68f., 75-76, 82, 96, 106, 111, 115, 17, 127, 211, 212, 225, 272, 286, 301, 312

Moore, W. Edgar, 90 96

Morison, Frank, 127, 326-327

Morris, Henry, 13

Mowinckel, Sigmund, 248

Neuhaus, Richard J., 225ff.

Niebuhr, Reinhold, 219

Ogden, Schubert M., 20

Olsen, Viggo, 328

Orr, James, 126

Pamphilus, Eusebius, 159

Pannenberg, Wolfhart, 67-68, 69, 72-76, 133, 141, 156, 210, 225-259, 307ff., 324-325

Paulus, Heinrich, 119-127

Perkins, Robert L., 185

Perrin, Norman, 9ff.

Pfleiderer, Ott, 146-171, 288

Pinnock, Clark, 255

Ramm, Bernard, 46, 91, 178, 195, 223, 248, 322

Ramsey, A.M., 6

Randall, John H., Jr., 155, 117, 186

Renan, Ernst, 116, 129, 288

Ricoeur, Paul, 33

Robinson, John A.T., 35, 118, 289, 330

Schaaffs, Werner, 38, 39, 40-47, 52, 54

Scharffer, Francis, 23-24, 67, 70, 73, 185

Schleiermacher, Friedrich, 114, 116, 28

Schonfield, Hugh, 127, 145

Schweitzer, Albert, 31, 116, 121, 122, 127, 148, 287

Smith, Wilbur M., 83, 96, 225, 286

Sparrow-Simpson, W. J., 131

Spinoza, Benedict, 36

Stone, Ronald J., 219

Stott, John R.W., 67, 7-, 328

Strauss, David F. 115, 121, 127-146, 287

Swinburne, Richard, 27-28, 44, 91, 103

Tacitus, Cornelius, 275

Tenney, Merrill, 5, 8

Thomas, Owen C., 84

Throckmorton, Burton H., 29, 31

Tillich, Paul, 117, 129, 144-145, 288

Tomlin, E.W.F., 86

Turner, Victor, 30

Urs von Balthasar, Hans, 199

Van Buren, Paul M., 69, 70, 144-145

VanderMolen, Ronald, 53

Vine, W.E., 217

Walsh, W.H., 50, 54-55

Weiss, Johannes, 138

Wells, H.G., 14

Wright, G. Ernest, 246

Yamauchi, Edwin, 15-16, 17, 58


 

 

ENDNOTES (by chapter)
(Note: Original Document Used Footnotes)

Part 1

Chapter 1

1. Willi Marxsen, The Resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth, translated by Margaret Kohl (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970), p.12. This quote from I Cor. 15:14 and other Biblical quotes in this work are from the Revised Standard Version of the Bible (New York: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1946, 1952).

2. Gunther Bornkamm, Jesus of Nazareth, translated by Irene and Fraser Mcluckey (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1960), p. 181.

3. Marxsen believes that it is not impossible to prove the resurrection (op. cit., pp. 112-113, 119, 122), but we still accept the offer of faith in Jesus even if he is dead (Ibid., pp. 128, 147). Bornkamm argues that the resurrection cannot be demonstrated or proven to have occurred (op.cit., pp. 180-186; especially pp. 180, 184). But we can still exercise faith in Jesus apart from any such proof of this type of reasoning later—how it can be held by some that one can have faith in Jesus whether or not he has risen (and even if he is still dead!).

4. Laurence Miller, Jesus Christ Is Alive (Boston: W.A. Wilde Company, 1949), p. 9.

5. Merrill C. Tenney, The Reality of the Resurrection (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1963), pp. 7-8.

6. Charles C. Anderson, The Historical Jesus: A Continuing Quest (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1972),

7. A.M. Ramsey, The Resurrection of Christ (Second edition; London and Glasgow: Collins, 1965), pp.9-11.

8. Daniel P. Fuller, Easter Faith and History (Grand Rapids: William Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1965), pp. 18, 19.

9. C.C. Dobson, The Empty Tomb and the Risen Lord (Second edition revised; London and Edinburgh: Marshall; Morgan and Scott, Ltd., n.d.), pp. 24-25.

10. Markus Barth and Verne H. Fletcher, Acquittal by Resurrection (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1964), Foreward, pp. V-VIII; cf. p. 3.

11. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 12.

12. Rudolf Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology”, in Kerygma and Myth, edited by Han Werner Bartsch, translated by Reginald H. Fuller (New York: Harper and Row Publishers, 1961), p. 39 referring to Acts 17:31.

13. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 169, referring to Acts 17:30f.; Fuller, op.cit., pp. 14-15, referring to Rom. 10:9.

14. Rudolf Bultmann, Theology of the New Testament, translated by Kendrick Grobel (new York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, n.d.), part I, p. 27, referring to Acts 2:36 and Rom. 1:4. Cf. also Fuller, op,cit,. P 15, referring to Acts 2:22-36.

15. Fuller, op.cit., pp. 15-16, referring to Rom. 1:4.

16. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 169, referring to Acts 16:30f.

17. Anderson, op,cit., p. 158-159, referring to Rom. 4:25, 10:9; cf. also Barth and Fletcher, op,cit., p. 4 and Tenney, op,cit., p. 8.

18. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 169.

19. James McLewan, Resurrection Then and New (Philadelphia and New York: J.B. Lippincott Company, 1967), p. 92; cf. 87 also.

20. It should be noted that neither form or redaction criticism is actually theology Rather, these are literary methods that have been used in diverse endeavors, such as in studying classical literature. They are therefore utilized here as literary approaches which are presently being applied to the New Testament. These methods are thus referred to as the current theological approach to the resurrection because they are employed by theologians and not because these disciplines are mistakenly being referred as theology themselves. For the relationship between form and redaction criticism, see Norm Perrin’s What is Redaction Crisitism?, edited by Dan O. Via (Philadelphia: Fortress Press 1971), p. 13 for instance.

21. The aforementioned The Resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth.

22. Reginald H. Fuller, The Formation of the Resurrection Narratives (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1971).

23. Perrin, op.cit., pp. 13-15. Some of Bultmann’s conclusions on the importance of the resurrection in the early church have already been noted above.

24. Rudolf Bultmann, “The Study of the Synoptic Gospels” in Form Criticism, translated by Frederick C. Grant (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962), pp. 11-76.

25. Bultmann, Ibid., pp. 36-63.

26. Ibid., p. 25.

27. Perrin, op.cit., pp. 1-3, 13.

28. Ibid., pp.3, 12-13.

29. Bornkamm’s belief in the importance of the resurrection for Christian theology has been noted above.

30. Some of Marxsen’s contributions to the current study of the resurrection have also been noted above.

31. Perrin, op.cit., pp. 25-39.

32. See. For instance, Marxsen’s and R. Fuller’s work above, footness 21 and 22 respectively, which are entirely devoted to the resurrection. Portions of many works have also dealt with this subject, like those of Bultmann and Bornkamm cited above, footnotes 12 and two, respectively.

33. C.S. Lewis’ work Miracles (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1965) deals with the resurrection on pp. 148-155.

34. J.N.D. Anderson has at least two writing dealing with the resurrection. See Christianity: The Witness of History(London: Tyndale Press, 1969), pp. 84-108 and the booklet The Evidence for the Resurrection (Downers Grove: Inter_Varsity Press, 1966).

35. Berger’s work, A Rumor of Angels (New York: Doubleday Publishing Company, 1970) does not deal directly with the resurrection, but rather with the possibility of miracles and Supernatural events occurring.

36. Cassels has written at least two books which deal with the question of the resurrection. See This Fellow Jesus (New York: Pyramid Publications, 1973), pp.64-90 and Christian Primer (New York: Doubleday and Company, Inc., 1967), pp. 23-26.

37. One of Morris’ books Many Infallible Proofs (Sandiego: Creation-Life Publishers, 1974_, devotes a chapter to the resurrection, pp. 88-97.

38. E.G. Wells, The Outline of History, (Two volumes; Garden City: Garden City Books, 1949), vol. I, pp. 539-540.

39. Shepard B. Clough, Nina G. Garsoian and David L. Hicks, A History of the Ancient World (Three columns; Boston: D.C. Heath and Company, 1967), vol. I, Ancient and Medieval, p. 127.

40. Paul L. Maier, First Easter (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1973).

41. Ibid., p. 93. The Italics are Maier’s.

42. “Can history tell us what actually happened on that crucial down?” (Ibid., p. 114. The italics are Maier’s).

43. Ibid., of especially pp. 93-122.

44. See, for instance, Paul L. Maier, Who Was Responsible for the Trial and Death of Jesus?” Christianity Today, April 12, 1974, pp. 8-11.

45. Paul L. Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, Christianity Today, March 28, 1975, pp. 4-6.

46. Ibid.

47. Edwin M. Yamauchi, “Easter—Myth, hallucination or History?”, Christianity Today, two parts, March 15, 1975, pp. 4-7 and March 29, 1975, pp. 12-16.

48. Ibid., March 15, 1974, pp. 4-6.

49. Ibid. , March 15, 1974, pp. 4-6.

50. Ibid. , p. 7 and March 29, pp. 12-16.

51. For instance, see John Warwick Montgomery’s, The Shape of the Past: An Introduction to Philosophical Historiography (Ann Arbor: Edwards Brothers, Inc. , 1962) and Where is History Going? (Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1969).

52. William Wand, Christianity: A Historical Religion? (Valley Forge: Judson Press, 1972).

53. Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., pp. 6.

54. Yamauchi, op.cit., March 29, 1974, p. 16.

55. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 71, 93.

56. Wand, op.cit., pp. 93-94; cf. also pp. 51-52, 70-71.

57. John Hick, Theology and Verification”, in Religious Language and the Problem of Religious Knowledge, edited by Ronald E. Santoni (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1968). This article first appeared in Theology Today, volume 17, 1960, pp. 12-31.

58. Ibid., pp. 367, 376.

59. Ibid., p. 375.

60. Ibid., pp. 371-375.

61. Ibid., pp. 368-369.

62. Ibid., pp. 376-381.

63. Cf. Ibid., pp. 375-376 for instance, where Hick admits that it would be easy to conceive of after-life experiences that would not at all verify theism, but he does not entertain the objections .

64. Ibid., pp. 367-368.

65. Schubert M. Ogden, “Toward a New Theism”, in Process Philosophy and Christian Thought, edited by Delwin Brown, Ralph E. James, Jr. and Gene Reeves (Indianapolis : The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1971), p. 183. Cf. also Ogden’s examination of a modern approach to the resurrection in his work The Reality of God and Other Essays (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966), pp. 215-220.

66. Bernard M. Loomer, “Christian Faith and Process Philosophy” in Process Philosophy and Christian Thought, Ibid., pp. 91, 95 for his treatment of the resurrection.

67. Peter N. Hamilton, “Some Proposals for a Modern Christology in Process Philosophy and Christian Thought, Ibid., pp. 371, 376, 379, 381.

68. Ibid., p. 379.

69. Ibid., pp. 379-380.

70. Ibid., pp. 378, 381.

71. Ibid., pp. 371, 375, 380.

72. Ibid., pp. 377-378.

73. Ibid., p. 378.

74. Francis Schaeffer, Escape from Reason (Downers Grove: Inter-Varsity Press, 1968_, see pp. 84-85 for instance.

75. Francis Schaeffer, The God Who is There, (Downers Grove: Inter-Varsity Press, 1968), pp. 112, 142.

76. Schaeffer, The God Who is There, Ibid., p. 92; see also Schaeffer’s Escape from Reason, op.cit., p. 77.

77. Schaeffer, Escape from Reason, Ibid., pp. 79, 90 and Schaeffer’s The Church Before the Watching World (Downer’s Gove: Inter-Varsity Press, 1971), pp. 98-99.

Chapter 2

1. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology”, in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 1-5.

2. Ibid., pp. 34-35, 39.

3. David Hume, Essential Works of David Hume, edited by Ralph Cohen (New York: Bantam Books, Inc., 1965), p. 128, footnote 3.

4. Richard Swinburne, The Concept of Miracle (London: Macmillan and St. Martin’s Press, 1970), p. 11.

5. Lewis, op.cit., p. 10.

6. Ibid., pp. 47, 60.

7. Ibid., pp. 148-169 for instance.

8. John McNaugher, Jesus Christ the Same Yesterday, Today and Forever (New York: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1947), pp. 01-92.

9. In the case of Bultmann we are referring to this scholar’s references to what “miracle” meant in the New Testament, as mentioned above. Like Hume he does not believe they occur, but grants that this was still believed to be the definition of the words in first century Christian thought.

10. For a very brief introduction to the question of some older theories concerning the origins of myth, see Daniel Dodson’s introductory essay “What is ‘Myth’?” in Thomas Bulfinch’s The Age of Fable (Greenwich: Fawcett Publications, Inc., 1961), pp. VI, IX. For an examination of the origins of myth according to many historians of religion, see Burtin H. Throckmorton’s The New Testament and Mythology (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1959), pp. 81-85.

11. Wand, op.cit., p. 40; see also James K. Feibleman’s article “Myth” in the Dictionary of Philosophy, edited by Dagobert Runes (Totowa: Littlefield, Adams and Company, 1967), p. 203.

12. Wand, Ibid.

13. Runes. op.cit., p. 203.

14. For instance, see Mircea Eliade, The Quest: History and Meaning in Religion (Chicago: The Unversity of Chicago Press, 1969), p. 72f. See also Throckmorton, op.cit., p. 80.

15. See Victor Turner’s article “Myth and Symbol” in the International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, edited by David L. Sills (no city: The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, 1968), vol. 10, pp. 576-582. For the definition of “myth” employed in literature, for example, see James F. Knapp, “Myth in the Powerhouse of Change”, The Centennial Review, Winter, 1976, pp. 56074. Cf. Wesley Barnes, The Philosophy and Literature of Existentialism (Woodbury: Barron’s Educational Series, 1968), pp. 34-40.

16. See S.H. Hooke, Middle Eastern Mythology (Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1966), who lists this view as one which is still employed in current treatments of this subject (p.11). See also Wand, op.cit., p. 40.

17. See Albert Schweitzer, The Question of the Historical Jesus, translated by W. Montgomery (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1968), pp. 78-79; cf. David Strauss’ work The Old Faith and the New, translated from the sixth edition by Mathilde Blind (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1874), pp. 56-59 for instance.

18. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth op.cit., especially pp. 1-11. Cf. Schubert Ogden, Christ Without Myth (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1961), pp. 39-40.

19. Throckmorton, op,cit., p. 23; cf. John Macquarrie, An Existentialist Theology (New York: Harper and Row, 1965), pp. 172-173.

20. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 10-11.

21. Mircea Eliade, Myth and Reality, translated by William R. Task (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1963), pp. 5-14.

22.Mircea Eliade, Mephistopheles and the Androgyne: Studies in Religious Myth and Symbol, translated by J.M. Cohen (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1965), pp. 201-208.

23. Hooke, op.cit., pp. 11, 16.

24. For Paul Ricoeur’s understand of the intermingling of theology and culture , see his work History and Truth, translated by Charles A. Kelbley (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1965), pp. 177-179 for example.

25. Hooke, op.cit., pp.19-32.

26. Wand, op,cit., p. 42.

27. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 1-10.

28. Ibid., p. 5.

29. Ibid., 4-5; cf. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., p. 194, especially footnote number 37.

30. Bultmann, Ibid., p. 38; cf. Macquarrie, op.cit., pp. 185-186.

31. Cf. for example John A.T. Robinson’s Honest to God (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1963), pp. 13-18.

32. James H. Jauncey, Science Return to God (Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1966), p. 37. C. also philosopher Gordon Clarks’ statements about the mechanism of the nineteenth century in his essay “Bultmann’s Three-Storied Universe” in Christianity Today, edited bu Frank E. Gaebelein (Westwood: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1968), pp. 218-219.

33. Benedict Spinoza, The Chief Works of Benedict De Spinoza, translated be R.E.M. Elwes (Two volumes; New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1951), vol. I, p. 87.

34. See Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Volume II, Number 2 of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, edited by Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap and Charles Morris (Unversity of Chicago Press, 1971)

35. Jauncey, op.cit., p. 3.

36. Ibid., pp. 37-38.

37. Clark, “Bultmann’s Three-Storied Universe” in Gaebelein, op-cit., pp. 218-219.

38. John Warwick Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology (Minneapolis: Bethany Fwlloship, Inc., 1970), pp. 320, 263.

39. Kuhn, op.cit., pp. 98ff.

40. Werner Schaaffs, Theology, Physics and Miracles, translated by Richard L. Renfield (Washington, D.C.: Canon Press, 1974) pp. 26, 31, 37-38. Cf. Jauncey, op.cit., p. 37.

41. Ibid., cf. pp. 25-26.

42. Ibid., cf. 24-26.

43. Ibid., pp. 63-64; cf. pp. 44-45.

44. Kuhn, op.cit., pp. 67, 149; cf. Schaaffs, Ibid., p. 64.

45. For instance, David Hume firmly rejected cause and effect. See O.W. Heick, History of Proestant Theology, Volume 2 of A History of Christian Thought by J.L. Neve ( Two volumes; Philadelphia: The Muhlenberg Press, The Western Intellectual Tradition (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962), p. 474.

46. Schaaffs, op.cit., pp. 63-64 and Clark, “Bultmann’s Three-Storied Universe” in Gaebelein, op,cit., p. 218.

47. Janucey, op.cit., pp. 37-38.

48. Ibid., p. 38; for this principle as it is applied to physics see Shaaffs, op,cit., pp. 57-61 and Otto Bluh and Joseph Denison Elder Principles and Applications of Physics (New York: Interscience Publishers, Inc., 1955), pp. 760ff.

49. Schaaffs, Ibid., p. 61.

50. Schaffs mentions three approaches in noting the effect of the microcosm on the macrocosm. One way would be to work from the microscopic elements to the macroscopic ones, noting the effect single atoms can have on whole processes or events. Or one might work in the opposite direction, beginning with the macrocosm and endeavoring to find the minute particles that affect it. Lastly, Schaffs has experimented with de Broglie’s equation of the matter-wave demonstrating that it can also be applied to the macrocosm, just as it can be applied to the microcosm (Ibid., pp. 80-81).

51. Ibid., pp. 52-53, 71, 79-81. This last point is illustrated by Schaaffs (pp. 52-53).

52. Ibid., pp. 16, 71. Cf. Bluh and Elder, op.cit., pp. 806-807, 803.

53. Schaaffs, op.cit., p. 64.

54. Jauncey, op,cit., p. 38.

55. Schaaffs, op,cit., p. 55.

56. Ibid., p. 56.

57. Ibid.

58. Ibid., p. 45.

59. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., p. 93; cf. pp. 73, 168-169.

60. Schaaffs, op.cit., p. 61.

61. Ibid., p. 65.

62. Schaaffs direct some of his criticisms against Bultmann (Ibid., pp. 13, 24-25) and other theologians who insist on using these outdated world views (Ibid., pp. 8, 15, 31, 60, 64).

63. Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., pp. 262-263.

64. See Schaaffs, op.cit,m pp. 64, 71; cf. also Swinburne, op.cit., pp. 23-26.

65. McNaugher, op.cit., p. 92; cf. of Swinburne, Ibid., pp. 26-29.

66. Note that we are showing the result on nature if miracles were to occur. We have not yet established of they actually do or not.

67. We wish to make it plain, however, that our study of contemporary physics is an extremely important one and not simply a “nice addition” to this work. Although this is based on an investigation of the facts to determine if an event has occurred and not upon a current scientific world view, this chapter has still provided some insight into the question of what is possible in today’s world. Understanding the current scientific outlook has demonstrated at least that our beliefs must not exclude miracles a priori. Also, it makes us realize that there is a scientific basis for our historical approach to investigating a purported event.

68. See Bernhard Ramm, Protestant Christian Evidences (Chicago: Moody Press, 1953), pp. 146-149.

69. Schaaffs, op.cit., p. 14. The italics are Schaaffs.

70. Ibid., p. 67.

71. Ibid., p. 14.

72. Cf. Ernest Cassirer, Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics, translated by O. Theodor Benfrey (New Haven: Yale University Press), p. 193 for instance.

73. Clark, “Bultmann’s Three-Storied Universe”, in Gaebelein, op.cit., pp. 218-219.

74. Ibid.

Chapter 3

1. See Patrick Gardiner’s article “The Philosophy of History” in the International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, edited by David L. Sills, op.cit., vol. 6, pp. 428-433 for some of these interpretations.

2. Most historians also recognize these two factors—the events themselves and the records of these events—as being an essential part of history. For such related views, see Carl L. Becker, The Heavenly City of Eighteenth-Century Philosophers (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1969), pp. 17-18; Bronwski and Mazlish, op.cit., pp. XI-XII; Clough, Garsoian and Hicks, op.cit vol. I, p. 1; Rune, op.cit., p.127; Want, op.cit., pp.22.

3. W.H. Walsh, Philosophy of History (New York: Harper and Brothers, Publishers, 1960), pp. 101, 103.

4. Wand, op,cit., pp. 29, 42.

5. Ibid., p. 31. See also Patrick Gardiner’s article “The Philosophy of History” in Sills, editor, op.cit., pp. 432-433.

6. Wand, op.cit., pp. 51-52.

7. Ernest Nagel, “Determinism in History” in Dray, op.cit., p. 355.

8. Ibid.

9. Ibid.

10. Ibid.

11. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., p. 71.

12. See Schaaffs, op.cit., cf. pp. 52-53, 64 for instance.

13. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 168-169.

14.Ronald VanderMolen, “’Where is History Going?’ and Historical Scholarship: A Response” in Fides et historia, Fall, 1972 and Spring, 1973, Vol. V, Nos. 1-2, p. 110.

15. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 71-74.

16. Wand, op.cit., pp. 25-27.

17. Ibid., pp. 30, 51-52, 156, 167.

18. Schaaffs, op.cit., p. 56.

19. Wand, op.cit., p. 5.

20. Walsh, op.cit., p. 18. For good example of such an investigation with regard to ancient historical events, see Delbruck’s methods of determining how ancient battles had been fought in the times of the Greek and Roman empires. It is fascinating to perceive how this scholar was able to arrive at historical facts concerning how large the opposing armies were, how they maneuvered and examining the ancient historical records. For instance, see Edward M. Earle, editor, Makers of Modern Strategy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1943), especially pp. 264-268 with regard to Delbruck’s historical method.

21. Ibid., pp. 18-19; cf. Daniel Fullerm op.cit., p. 22 for these same conclusions.

22. John Warwick Montgomery, History and Christianity (Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 1972), p. 75 Cf. also Montgomery’s Where is History Going? op.cit., p. 71.

23. Ibid., cf. also Where is History Going?, pp. 168-169.

24. Wand, op.cit., pp. 30, 101.

25. Ibid., pp. 51-52.

26. Ibid., pp. 70-71.

27. Ibid., pp. 29-31.

28. Ibid., p. 35.

29. Ibid., pp. 17-18.

30. Ibid., p. 42.

31. Ibid., pp. 29-31.

32. Ibid., pp. 80, 114.

33. Ibid., pp. 90-94.

34. Maier, First Easter, op.cit., pp. 105-122 and “The Empty Tomb as History”, op,cit., pp. 4-6.

35. Yamauchi, op.cit,. March 15, 1974 pp 4-7 and March 29, 1974, pp. 12-16.

36. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 71-73, 93, 168-169 for instance.

37. It is important to note that historical studies have also been made about other miracle-claims in ancient history. N>I> Finley, for instance, investigates Homer and his claims of miraculous intervention into early history, such as with the Trojan war. Or for another example, various scholars have examined claims of tongue-speaking, or glossolalia, in ancient history. For Finley’s work, see The world of Odysseus (New York: The Viking Press, 1954), especially pp. 10-19. For a historical discussion of speaking in tongues, see George Barton Cutten, Speaking with Tongues Historically and Psychologically Examined (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1927), pp. 36-47 for instance. For another example, see Frank Stagg, E. Glenn Hinton and Wayne E. Oates, Glossolalia: Tongue Speaking in Biblical, Historical and Psychological Perspective, (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1967), pp. 48-57.

Chapter 4

1. See Manfred T. Brauch, “Head and Heart God to Seminary”, Christianity Today, June 20, 1975, pp. 11-12.

2. Etienne Gilson, Reason and Revelation in the Middle Ages (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1966).

3. Ibid., pp. 9-10.

4. Ibid., pp. 12-13.

5. Ibid., pp. 17-19.

6. Ibid., pp. 17-19.

7. Ibid., pp. 37-62. See especially pp. 42-48.

8. Ibid., see especially pp. 82-83.

9. This writer realizes that philosophical conclusions such as these cannot be based solely on dictionary definitions. Since dictionaries only show how a word is used by most intelligent people, we would be epistemologically naive of we were to assume that such definitions are capable of settling these philosophical issues. Nevertheless, such an approach can be very valuable as a groundwork for later conclusions and this is how these definitions are to be used here. They serve as guidelines for the more sophisticated scholarly views which will be presented afterwards to further corroborate these usages. The definitions themselves can point to a consensus of opinion as they reveal how these words are often defined. However this will be corroborated by later references to scholars who verify these statements.

10. William Morris, editor, The American heritage Dictionary of the English Language (New York: American Heritage Publishing Company, Inc. and the Houghton Mifflin Company, 1970), 1086.

11. Ibid.

12. Ibid., p. 471.

13. Cf. Ibid., p. 121.

14. Ibid., p. 1086.

15. One may object that many have exercised religious faith because they were told to do so or for other reasons which require no real contemplation. But we would hold that if one was capable of understanding his faith he would have been required to have thought about it at some time, if only in a naïve and simple way. This is because faith would even involved affirmation of what others have dictated. However simple, it would be an acceptance at least some thinking as a part of this conviction or it could not be said to be such. For this reason, if one has never thought about his belief in any way it can only be because real faith was never exercised in the first place.

16. Morris, op.cit., p. 1086.

17. Ibid.

18. Cf. the New Testament’s primary emphasis on faith in such verses as Jn. 20:29; Eph. 2:8; Heb. 11:1, 6.

19. Paul M. Van Buren, The Secular Meaning of the Gospel (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1963), pp. 174-175.

20. John R.W. Stott, Your Mind Matters: The Place of the Mind in the Christian Life (Downers Grove: Inter-Varsity Press, 1973), pp. 33-36.

21. Ibid., pp. 34, 36, 49-52.

22. Schaeffer, The God Who is There, op.cit., pp. 112-113, 141-143.

23. These two essays are found in one of Pannenberg's collections of other such works entitled Basic Questions in Theology, translated by George H. Kehm (Two volumes; Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1972), see vol. II, pp. 28-35, 53-54 for instance. We will further elaborate on Pannenberg’s theories on reason and faith below.

24. See the appendix of History of Christianity, op.cit pp. 99-101, 106-108. Cf. also Montgomery’s debate with “God is dead” theologian Thomas Altizer, where Montgomery charges that Altizer’s irrational faith provides no reason for others to believe him because it is based on no objective evidence. This debate is recorded in The Altizer-Montgomery Dialogue (Chicago: InterVarsity Press, 1967). See pp. 26, 59-60, 72, 76 and others where this charge is made. As with Pannenberg, so we will return to this reasoning below.

25. Even the case of atheism is no exemption here. If one designates atheism as a “religious faith”, then it still must be acknowledged that it is also based on the knowledge of certain facts which are believed to be true. In the case this would be the non-existence of God.

26. Cf. Van Buren, op.cit., pp. 174-175; Stott, op.cit., p. 57; Schaeffer, The God Who is There, op.cit., pp. 143-145; Pennenberg, op,cit., vol. II, pp. 37, 45; Montgomery, History and Christianity, op,cit., pp. 106-108. It is extremely important to note here, in addition, that the reason or knowledge upon which faith is based is not always a very sophisticated one. As asserted in footnote number 15 above, faith must be based on some knowledge, told. But even in this case acceptance of belief in God (or whatever it is that one it told to believe) still involves the acceptance of the knowledge that these beliefs are true. Anything sort of this is not real faith. At no point in this work is the assertion ever made that one mist be capable of a logical investigation of the facts before one can believe. Such is clearly not the case. A reasonable faith can be shown to be more valuable but a faith based upon a less sophisticated knowledge is not thereby invalid. If the Christian faith can be shown to be based on a logical investigation of the facts, then faith in these facts is valid even if one is not capable of demonstrating the evidence for oneself.

27. Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 32, footnote and also Wolfhart Pannenberg, editor, Revelation as History, translated by David Granskou (New York: Macmillan Company, 1969), pp. 139, 157, note 15. Cf. Schaeffer, Ibid.

28. See Stott, op.cit., p. 57.

29. Van Buren, op.cit., p. 174.

30. Stott, op.cit., p. 37.

31. See Schaeffer, The God Who is There, op.cit., pp. 141-143.

32. Ibid., pp. 112-113.

33. Montgomery, History and Christianity, op.cit., p. 101; cf. pp. 99, 107.

34. It might be objected that perhaps one does not care to make his faith obligatory for others, thus keeping it simply on the subjective level, But here we must remember, first interested in bringing others to accept this same grace of God that it has received. It therefore does not thrive on one’s keeping faith to oneself, Second, we have reasoned here that Christianity is most properly based on one’s exercising faith as a result if facts which are believed to be true and not upon irrational explanations or private experiences apart from these facts. Thus this aforementioned objection falls prey both to the idea that the Christian faith is to be propagated and to the conviction that faith is based upon objective facts as opposed to subjective feelings. For some of these ideas see Pannenberg’s Basic Questions in Theology, op,cit., vol. II, especially pp. 53-54; cf. pp. 28, 30-32.

35. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 135-139.

36. Ibid., especially p. 138. See also Basic Question in Theology, op.cit., vol. II, pp. 30, 53-54.

37. See Pannenberg’s Basic Question in Theology,, Ibid., vol. II, pp. 33-34.

38. Schaeffer, The God Who is There, op.cit., p. 141; cf. p. 92.

39. Montgomery, History and Christianity, op.cit., 75-76, 79-80, 107-108.

40. Ibid., p. 107.

41. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 137.

42. Pannenberg, Basic Question in Theology, po.cit., vol. II, p. 48.

43. Ibid., p. 37 and Revelation as History, op,cit., pp. 137-139.

44. Montgomery, History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 79-80, 107.

45. Wand, op.cit., p. 34.

46. Ibid.

47. Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology, op,cit., vol. II, pp. 36-37.

48. Ibid., pp. 34-35, 47.

49. Brauch, op.cit., p.12..

50. Schaeffer, The God Who is There, op,cit., p. 113 and Pannanberg, Basic Questions in Theology, op.cit., vol. II, p. 28.

51. Notice that in all three instances we have concluded that probabilities play a decisive part. Science has demonstrated the need to explain issues statistically, thus relying on this procedure as the best method of discerning facts about the past. Even in the philosophical treatment of reason and faith we spoke of the importance of faith making its decision on the probability of the rational investigation. Thus faith acts upon the most probable solution as well, We have here a striking confirmation of this belief.

Part 2

Chapter 5

1. In each of the three possible approaches to the resurrection which are covered in this work, we will likewise concentrate on one major scholar who we think is a representative example of that view. In the introductions to each chapter we will also outline the reasons for such choices. However, we will not be confined to just these three single opinions but in all three instances we will also entertain other similar view in the next chapter.

2. See for example, McNaugher’s treatment of miracles, which also deals with Hume’s essay, op.cit., pp. 91-118.

3. Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., p. 38.

4. Wilbur M. Smith, The Supernaturalness of Christ (Boston: W.A. Wilde Company, 1954), p. 142.

5. Later we will deal more fully with Hume’s influence on theology, specifically viewing other scholars who also reject all miraculous events and who believe that Hume’s essay is the apex of critical thought on this subject.

6. Heick, op.cit., p. 52. Heick does note, however, that Hume differed from deism at several points, such as the reliance upon reason and the desire to prove the existence of God. By turning from such notions, Hume contributed to the demise of deism by taking this stance in favor of empiricism. (Ibid., pp. 65-66).

7. Ibid.

8. Ibid., pp. 51-52; cf. also Vergilius Ferm’s article “Deism” in Runes, op.cit., p. 75.

9. This essay can be found in Owen C. Thomas, editor, Attitudes Toward Other Religions (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers 1969), pp. 32-46. Of course, not all scholars of this period held to all of these more radical beliefs. For instance, see John Lock’s The Reasonableness of Christianity, edited by I.T. Ramsey (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1958), Cf, here also Form, “Deism”, in Runes. Ibid.

10. Heick, op.cit., pp. 53-58, 65.

11. Ibid., pp. 66.

12. See Hume’s position in his work edited by Cohen, op,cit., pp 124-125.

13. Becker, op.cit., pp. 38-39; cf. pp. 33-35.

14. David Hume, The History of England (Six volumes; London: Gilbert and Revington, Printers, 1848).

15. E.W.F. Tomlin, The Western Philosophers (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1967), pp. 194-195.

16. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., p. 128. See the discussion of Hume’s definition of miracle above. We will also return to this topic in the critique below. It is important to note here that this is not an obscure essay by Hume. This well known essay on miracles is Section X of his work An Enquiry Concerning Human Undertanding. See Ibid., pp. 123-142.

17. Ibid., pp. 125-129. See Edwin A. Burtt, Types of Religious philosophy (Revised edition; New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1939), pp. 212-216. Cf. Swinburne, op.cit., pp. 13-14.

18. Burtt, Ibid., p. 258.

19. Hume “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., pp. 129-14; cf. Swinburne, op.cit., pp. 15-18.

20. Hume Ibid., p. 128.

21. Ibid.

22. Ibid., p. 124.

23. Ibid., p. 125.

24. Lewis, op.cit., p. 105.

25. W. Edgar Moore, Creative and Critical Thinking (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1967), p. 188 for instance.

26. Cf. Swinburn, op.cit., p. 15 and Ramm, op.cit., pp. 126-128.

27. See McNaugher, op.cit., p. 92.

28. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., see pp. 127-129, 133, 139.

29. Cf. Lewis, op.cit., p. 60, McNaugher, op.cit., pp. 99-103 and Ramm, op.cit., p. 128, for instance.

30. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, po.cit., see the obvious examples of this attitude on pp. 127-128, 139.

31. See Lewis’ essay “The Laws of Nature”, contained in a collection of some of his other works of this type entitled God in the Dock, edited by Walter Hooper (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1973), pp. 76-79, especially p. 77.

32. Lewis, Miracles, op.cit., p. 106.

33. See Burtt, op.cit., p. 213, footnote 5 where it is also asserted that Hume fails to entertain this view which allows God to interfere with nature’s pattern from outside the system.

34. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., p. 128.

35. Ibid.

36. Ibid. The italics are Hume’s.

37. See McNaugher, op.cit., p. 101 for a similar charge against Hume.

38. Moore, op.cit., pp. 13-20.

39. Montgomery agrees that Hume’s a priori and circular argument obligates no one to accept such a view of experience (Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., p. 38).

40. Smith, op.cit., p. 147; McNaugher, op.cit., pp. 101-103.

41. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., p. 124.

42. Smith, op.cit., p. 146.

43. Burtt, op.cit., p. 215.

44. Lewis, Miracles, op.cit., p. 106.

45. Hume asserts that these four supportive points, which are summarized above, prove all miracles to be untrustworthy. We will briefly restate these four here. First, no historical accounts of miracles are attested by enough reputable witnesses. Second, people delight in telling miraculous stories, even lying in order to spread these teachings. Third, miracles are found mostly among people of backward nations. Fourthly, accounts of miracles in one religion nullify the accounts of those in other belief system. See Hume’s essay “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume., op.cit., pp. 129-134.

46. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., pp. 135-137, especially footnote number two.

47. Ibid.

48. Our purpose here is by no means to determine if these Jansenist miracles actually occurred or not. Rather, we purpose to determine exactly what Hume’s own reaction is when a miracle admittedly fulfills his four conditions. This we will perceive later.

49. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., pp. 135-137.

50. Ibid., p. 136.

51. Ibdi., pp. 134-135.

52. Ibid., p. 137. However, Hume seems to believe that just because the fourth point does not hold in this instance because of the superior testimony of the authorities involved (Ibid.), it still may apply in other instances (Ibid., pp. 137-138).

53. Hume, Ibid., pp. 135-136.

54. We must state here once again that we are not ourselves concerned as to whether these Jansenist claims are valid or not.

55. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., p. 137.

56. Ibid., p. 139 for instance.

57. Philosopher Swinburne arrives at similar conclusions about this exact passage in Hume’s work. He also realizes that Hume dismisses the Jansenist miracles not because the evidence is seen to be irrelevant (op.cit., p. 16). We might wonder just how Hume is able to disregard such an admittedly adequate amount of experience for these events when such examination and research is the foundation of history. The acceptance of past events as having actually occurred in based upon the existence of an adequate amount of historical evidence. But even though Hume realizes that such has been produced he still rejects the miracle, as Swinburne also notes. Such a double standard of rejecting miracles when they are evidence by the same (or even greater) amount of experience which is viewed as being adequate in other instances of establishing historical fact certainly seems unscholarly. It is such circular reasoning that invalidates his argument.

58. Hume , “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit,., pp. 128-129.

59. Ibid., pp. 132, 134.

60. Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., pp. 43-44, note 13.

61. If such miracles can be shown to exist, of course. We are still not making any judgment about the facticity of the Jansenist miracles, or saying that they are probable. This is because we have not investigated the evidence for ourselves. As mentioned above, the main object here was to perceive how Hume viewed occurrences which he thought were well-documented. This was accomplished here.

62. For Hume’s rejection of cause and effect, see, for instance, his work entitled A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1964), Book I, Part III, Section II, pp. 73-78, especially p. 76. Cf. also Heick, op.cit., p. 65.

63. David Hume, An Abstract of A Treatise of Hume Nature (Cambridge: The University Press, 1938). For a perceptive discussion concerning the author of this work, see the Introduction by J.M. Keynes and P. Spaffa, pp. V-XXXI; cf. Bronowski and Mazlish, op.cit., p. 474, footnote number three.

64. Hume, Ibid., especially p. 16. Cf. Bronowski and Mazlish, Ibid., pp. 474-475.

65. Cf. Bronowski and Mazlish, Ibid. See chapter two above.

66. Hume, “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cit., p. 128.

67. Ibid.

68. Ibid., p. 139.

69. Lewis, Miracles, op.cit., pp. 105-106.

70. Hume’s rejection of cause and effect has been noted above. For his emphasis on probability, see, for instance, his work Essays, Literary, Moral and Political (London: Ward, Lock and Bowden, Limited, n.d.), pp. 341-343 and also the essay “Of Miracles” in Essential Works of David Hume, op.cti., pp. 125-129.

71. Montgomey also feels that Hume’s argument against miracles is based on a closed view of the universe. See Montgomery’s Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., pp. 262-263, 351, note 15. Once again, we also believe that these are laws in nature, as pointed out above. To speak of miracles as out of the ordinary there must be an ordinary course of nature. The question is not if these laws exist, but if they can be temporarily suspended.

72. Even William Horden, a scholar sympathetic to certain trends in contemporary, critical theology, states that Hume argues circularly in this essay. See his work A Layman’s Guide to Protestant Theology (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1956), p. 37.

Chapter 6

1. Briefly, we will refer to religious liberalism in this work as the predominant trend of theological thought in the nineteenth century (cf. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., chapter three). More specifically we might date this movement’s prominence from the publishing of Schleiermacher’s work On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers in 1799 to Karl Barth’s The Epistle to the Romans which appeared in 1918. Cf. here this work by Schleiermacher, translated by John Oman (New York: Harper and Brothers, Publishers, 1958). See the Introduction by Rudolf Otto, especially pp. IX, XII. Cf. also Burtt, op.cit, p. 284 and William Hordern, Introduction, Volume I of New Directions in Theology Today, edited by William Hordern (Seven volumes; Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1966), p. 15.

2. John Herman Randall, Jr., The Making of the Modern Mind (Revised edition; Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1940), pp. 553-554. Concerning Randall’s statement that liberalism rejected miracles because of the influence of Hume’s essay, it appears that Randall is also speaking of liberalism as a predominately nineteenth century movement (Ibid).

3. Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op,cit pp. 27-28.

4. David Friedrich Stauss, A New Life of Jesus, no translator given (Second edition; two volumes; London: Williams and Norgate, 1879), vol. I, p. 199.

5. Ibid., pp. 199-201.

6. Friedrich Schleiermacher, The Christian Faith, edited by H. R. Mackintosh and J. S. Stewart (Two volumes; New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1963), vol. I, pp. 71, 178-184; vol. II, pp. 448-449.

7. Schleiermacher, On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despiser, op.cit., pp/ 88-89, 113-114, explanation number 16.

8. Albert Schweitzer, The Quest of the Historical Jesus, translated from the 1906 German edition, op.cit., p. 154.

9. Ernst Renan, Life of Jesus, volume one of The History of the Origins of Christianity, no translator given (London: Mathieson and Company, n.d.), pp. 147-155, especially p. 148.

10. Adolf Harnack, What is Christianity?, translated by Thomas Bailey Saunders (Third and revised edition; London: Williams and Norgate, 1912), pp. 25-31.

11. Randall asserts that from Hume’s time until today few learned men have questioned his conclusions against miracles (op.cit., p. 293).

12. Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., pp. 37-38; cf. p. 28.

13. Paul Tillich, Systematic Theology (Three volumes; Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1971), vol. I, pp. 115-117. Cf. Alexander J, McKelway, The Systematic Theology of Paul Tillich (New York: Dell Publishing Company, Inc., 1964), pp. 81-83.

14. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 4-5-.

15. John A.T. Robinson, Honest to God (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1963), pp. 11-18, 64-68.

16. Heick, op.cit., pp. 92-102, 119-127; especially p. 92.

17. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 38; cf. Schweitzer, op.cit., pp. 51, 53.

18. Schweitzer, Ibid., pp. 49, 51-53.

19. Ibid., pp. 53-55.

20. For some of those who held this view, see Ibid., pp. 46-47, 64, 161-166; cf. pp. 43, 60.

21. Ibid., p. 38.

22. Cf. Ibid., pp. 48-50.

23. Strauss, op.cit., vol. I, p. 412.

24. Schweitzer, op.cit., p. 54.

25. Cf., for instance, McNaugher, op.cit., p. 148; Smith, op.cit p. 208; Miller, op.cit., [[/ 37-38.

26. Schweitzer, op.cit., p. 56.

27. Renan, op.cit., pp. 244-245.

28. Anyone who has had the misfortune of even stepping on a nail knows the discomfort and pain so caused, including the forced limp! This writer has done do so several times. Once only a small nail was enough to incapacitate him for three days, making it impossible to recover completely until the fourth and fifth day. Imagine the results of crucifixion with a spike bearing one’s weight for several hours! We could not avoid Strauss’ illustration of the condition in which a wounded crucifixion victim would emerge from the grave. Considering the feet only (even if we were to momentarily disregard the other wounds), it would not be possible to walk so soon afterwards. Detection of such a wounded victim would indeed be both inescapable and inevitable. He would not pass for someone who was resurrected, ay any rate.

29. This portion is quoted from Maier’s The First Easter, op.cit., pp. 78, 80. Page 79 contains three photographs of the above-mentioned crucified victim’s bones which were affected by the piercing of the nails.

30. Ibid., p. 79.

31. For the most likely reasoning behind the breaking of these men’s legs in order to speed up their deaths, see Jim Bishop’s analysis in The Day Christ Died (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1965), cf. p. 280 with pp. 289-290.

32. For a few of those who hold one of these views, see Renan, op.cit., p. 244-245; McNaugher, op.cit., p. 148; Miller, op.cit., pp. 38-39; Charles C. Anderson, op.cit., p. 168; Mair, op.cit., p. 112.

33. Maier, The First Easter, op.cit., p. 80.

34. For this last point, see Charles C. Anderson, op.cit., p. 168.

35. Cf. Miller, op.cit., p. 38.

36. What of Jesus’ embalmed body? Could he move the stone in front of the tomb? How and where did he actually die? Questions such as these are most difficult for this theory. Cf. Charles C. Anderson, op.cit., p. 168.

37. McNaugher, op.cit., p. 149.

38. James Orr, The Resurrection of Jesus (Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1908 edition reprinted in 1965), p. 92.

39. Karl Barth, The Doctrine of Reconciliation, Volume IV, Part One of Church Dogmatics, edited by G.W. Bromiley and T.F. Torrance (13 volumes; Edinburgh: T. and T. Clark, 1961), pp. 340-341.

40. Frank Morison, Who Moved the Stone? (London: Faber and Faber Limited 1962), p. 96. It is true that this theory reappears from time to time, almost always establishing many of the older presuppositions and often, once again, in the form of a novel. One such modern attempt is Hugh Schonfield’s The Passover Plot (New York: Bantam Books, Inc., 1967). That such attempts to revive this theory are generally met with scholarly disdain (see, for instance, Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., p. 39 and especially note number 44 on p. 46 and J.N.D. Anderson, op.cit., pp. 63-65; cf. pp. 93-94) is easily conceivable since this theory still has to adequately answer the objections raised here and other similar problems.

41. Schweitzer, op.cit., pp. 71-72, 96-120. Cf. Charles C. Anderson, Critical Question of Jesus (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1969), p. 18.

42. Schweitzer, Ibid., pp. 70-72, 96-97, 111.

43. Strauss, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 199-201; vol. II, pp. 149-280. Cf. Schweitzer, Ibid., pp. 82-83.

44. Strauss, Ibid., vol. I, pp. 408-412.

45. Ibid., vol. I, pp. 427-429; cf. also Strauss’ work The Old Faith and the New, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 81-82.

46. Strauss, The New Life of Jesus, Ibid., vol. I, pp. 430-437 and The Old Faith and the New, Ibid.

47. Strauss, The New Life of Jesus, Ibid., vol. I, p. 440.

48. Strauss, The Old Faith and the New, op.cit., vol. I, p. 83.

49. Renan, op.cit., pp. 249, 309-310; Schweitzer, op.cit., pp. 170, 187. Renan’s work has already been cited above. Ghillany, writing an imaginative life of Jesus under the pseudonym of Richard von der Alm, also preferred this view. Other liberals accepted this theory as well.

50. Comparatively few scholars hold the vision theory today. More common are the views which are based upon some personal experience of the disciples which convinced them that Jesus was somehow still alive. The exact details vary from one view to the next. Charles Anderson (The Historical Jesus: The Continuing Quest,, op.cit., pp. 169-171) and Paul Maier (First Easter, op.cit., p. 107) rightly include such views in the same category with the vision theory because, even though hallucinations are rejected here, a subjective experience of one sort or another is generally perceived to be based upon some form of pre-existent faith on the part of the disciples. Thus it is still a case of these believers becoming convinced of the resurrection because of their own projected faith issuing forth into a belief in objective reality. Probably he best-known theory of this type is Paul Tillich’s “restitution theory”. For Tillich, the resurrection is not to be conceived of in terms of the reappearance of either a person or a spirit. In fact it is any type of literal appearance of any kind. Rather, the disciples experienced the spiritual presence of Jesus. Like Strauss, Tillich feels that it was actually an ecstatic experience which convinced them that Jesus was the New Being. It is possible for believers today to have this same experience (Tillich, op.cit., vol. II, pp. 156-158. For a similar interpretation of Tillich’s view, see Mckelway, op.cit., pp. 170-171, 181-182). Theories such as Tillich’s will also be included in this treatment of visions (as Charles Anderson and Paul Maier also do). Most of the problems involved in postulating a pre-existent faith and in the subsequent application of subjective criteria to objective conviction also apply here and render sich an experience quite impossible, as will be shown below.

51. Schleiermacher, The Christian Faith, op.cit., vol. II, p. 420.

52. Schweitzer, op.cit., pp. 54-55.

53. Ibid., pp. 193, 211.

54. See, for instance, Strauss’ The New Life of Jesus, op.cit., vol. I, p. 440.

55. W.J. Sparrow-Simpson, The Resurrection and the Christian Faith (Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1911 edition reprinted in 1965), pp. 113-115. The theory popularized by Keim is commonly referred to as the “telegram theory” According to this hypothesis, Jesus rose spiritually from the dead (not bodily) and returned to God. Afterwards he communicated the knowledge of his spiritual existence to the apostles by means of “telegrams” of messages from heaven. The appearances of Jesus recorded in the New Testament were therefore not subjective visions of hallucinations but objective impressions sent by both Jesus and God. Keim admits that this communication to the disciples of the truth that Jesus had risen required Divine intervention (Ibid., pp. 117, 119; McNaugher, op.cit/. pp. 155-156). But such a theory falls prey to at least four major criticisms. First, is this view any less a miracle than the view recorded in the New Testament? The miraculous is admittedly involved here as well as still have the teaching that Jesus actually rose and is alive (although in spiritual form). Second, would God and the risen Jesus send messages and reveal appearances which would deceive the disciples into thinking that Jesus was physically there with them? Such deception has moral (or amoral!) implications and fails to explain why Jesus did not actually appear instead of sending the impression that he had actually done so. Third, these impressions would not be objective enough to make them think that Jesus had actually risen bodily. Fourth, it fails to explain the empty tomb. (For these and similar criticisms, see Tillich, op.cit., vol. II, p. 156; McNaugher, Ibid.; Lewis, Miracles, op.cit., pp. 152-153; Smith, op.cit., pp. 219-220; Tenney, op.cit., pp. 189-192.)

56. Sparrow-Simpson, Ibid., pp. 113-115; Orr, op.cit., p. 219; McNaugher, Ibid., p. 155.

57. McNaugher, Ibid., p. 152. See especially George E. Ladd, I Believe in the Resurrection of Jesus (Grand Rapids: William E. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1975), p. 138.

58. Wolfhart Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, translated by Lewis L. Wilkins and Duane A. Priebe (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1968), p. 96.

59. Ibid.

60. Raymond E. Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus (New York: Paulist Press, 1973), p. 84.

61. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 116.

62. William Barclay, The Mind of Jesus (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1961), pp. 304-405.

63. Ramsey, op.cit., p. 41.

64. Strauss, The New Life of Jesus, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 430-431. Cf. also Sparrow-Simpson, op.cit., pp. 111-112.

65. McNaugher, op.cit., p. 116.

66. McNaugher, op.cit., p. 152

67. The narratives sufficiently establish this point. See Luke 24:12, 21; Jn. 20:9, 19; cf. the Markan appendix, 16:10. Cf. also Brown, op.cit p. 106, footnote number 176.

68. Ramsey, op.cit., p 41.

69. The witness to this is even greater than that of the previous point. See Matt. 28:17; Luke 24:11, 22-24, 27; Jn. 20:25; 21:4; Cf. the Markan appendix, Mk. 16:11, 13, 14. Cf. also Brown, op.cit., p. 106, footnote number 176.

70. Orr, op.cit., p 225.

71. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 81-82; cf. pp. 100-101.

72. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 67.

73. Ramsey, op.cit., p. 41.

74. Even Gordon Kaufman, one of the comparatively few scholars who still hold the vision theory today, realizes that a prior belief must exist before visions can be produced. However, he fails to show what positive factors there were that would be sufficient to give rise to this optimistic faith, a which would absolutely have to be present before the events themselves. This is quite damaging to his viewpoint, especially in view of the fact that he admits that the disciples were quite disillusioned at Jesus’ death and were therefore subject to despair. He realizes that their hope had disappeared. But we may wonder what spontaneous factors caused such a reversal of thought and made the disciples believe that Jesus was alive before they received any confirmation of the fact. See these admissions in Kaufman’s Systematic Theology: A Historical Perspective (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1963), especially pp. 415, 422.

75. Ibid., p. 421; footnote 20; Orr, Orr., p. 219.

76. Edwin G. Boring, Herbert S. Landfield and Harry P. Weld, editors, Foundations of Psychology (New York: John Wiley and Sons, Inc., 1956), p. 216; Yamauchi, op.cit., March 15, 1974, p. 6; McNaugher, op.cit., p. 153; Smith, op.cit., p. 217.

77. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., pp. 96-97.

78. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mthology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 42. See Orr, op.cit., p. 115, with regards to this admission by critic Kirsopp Lake.

79. Johannes Weiss, Earliest Christianity: A History of the Period A.D. 30-150, edited by Frederick C. Grant (Two volumes; Magnolia: Peter Smith, Publishers 1959), vol. I, p. 28.

80. Bultmann, Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 39; cf. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 29. See also Archibald T. Robertson, Word Pictures in the New Testament (Six volumes; Nashville: Broadman Press, 1931), vol. IV, p. 188.

81. Brown, op.cit., p.91.

82. See Ramsey, op.cit., pp. 61-62.

83. Orr, op.cit., p. 176. Cf. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 107.

84. This conclusion was verified for the writer by a discussion with a psychology professor on Dec. 18, 1969, who spoke of the various impossibilities of relying on visions in this instances.

85. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 97.

86. Sparrow-Simpson, op.cit., p. 114.

87. See Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 32, 170.

88. Sparrow-Simpson, op.cit., p. 114.

89. See for instance, William James, The Principles of Psychology (Two volumes; David Publications, Inc., 1950), vol. II, pp. 114-115. Cf. also Yamauchi, op.cit., March 15, 1974, p. 6 and Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 95.

90. Yamauchi, Ibid,; Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 94-95, footnote number 93.

91. Kaufman admits that the objection that the vision theory is too subjective to account for such objective appearances of Jesus is a strong one. He also notes that his work had thus far (op.cit., pp. 426-427) not sufficiently handled this problem.

92. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 95-97.

93. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 67; Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 81-82; cf. pp. 100-101; Brown, op.cit., pp. 84, 106, footnote 176.

94. Reginald Fuller, Ibid., pp. 32, 170. Cf. Marxsen, Ibid., pp. 100-102.

95. See, for example, Orr, op.cit p. 197. See also Reginald Fuller, Ibid., pp. 71-154.

96. Luke 24:36-43 relates this scene. The disciples though that they were viewing a bodiless apparition or spirit (Greek pneuma; cf. Matt. 14:26, 27). Jesus had to convince them otherwise by presenting his body for observation, We are told that they only believed that they were not seeing “ghosts” when it was thus proven to them. See Robertson, op.cit., vol. II, p. 296. Other verses where it is either stated or implied that Jesus’ body was handled include Matt. 28:9; John 20:17, 26-28; cf. Acts 1:3.

97. Cf. Robert H, Grant; Miracle and Natural Law (Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company, 1952), pp. 229-230; Brown, op.cit., pp. 85-89; Charles Anderson, op.cit., pp. 161, 163-166; Smith, op.cit., pp. 194-195. Concerning Paul’s list being based upon eyewitness testimony, see Brown, Ibid., p. 92 and Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 28-29.

98. Brown, Ibid., pp. 91; Ladd; op.cit., p. 138; cf. p. 105.

99. Cf. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 39 and Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 29.

100. This is also reported by Ignatius in section three of his Epistle to the Smyrneans. See J.E. Lightfoot, editor and translator, The Apostolic Fathers (Grand Rapids: Baker Book Hourse, 1971), p. 83; cf. p. 85.

101. See Sparrow-Simpson, op.cit., p. 110.

102. Orr, op.cit., p. 180.

103. For instance, if the vision theory were true, the empty tomb would be left unexplained. And what happened to Jesus’ body? In addition, this writer has complied a list of 34 total reasons why this theory is inadequate.

104. Theories like those of Tillich (op.cit., vol. II, pp. 156-158) and Van Buren (op.cit., pp. 132-133) which rely on some unexplained subjective experience of the disciples face practically all of the same difficulties. For instance, the disciples’ despondency and doubt must still be changed to faith before the experience itself in order for these to occur in the first place, which encounters the difficulties raised above. There is likewise manner, as well as with the various time and place factors. Even more acute is the disciples’ mistaking such subjective experiences for objective ones and how they became convinced that Jesus had literally risen from the dead. The disciples knew the difference between the resurrection appearances and later experiences, as explained above. We also find psychological causes lacking here. What would give rise to such experiences? As with visions, there is also the objection that cautions were deliberately taken in the narratives to prove that the experiences were objective and not subjective. These are a few of the key objections to these subjective. These are a few of the key objections to these subjective. These are a few of the key objections to these subjective theories, As we have observed, they are practically the same as those listed above. See McKelway (op.cit., pp. 170-171, 181-183), Charles Anderson (op.cit., pp. 169-173) and Maier (The First Easter, op.cit., pp. 112-113) for similar criticisms and other objections to this theory.

105. Orr, op.cit., pp. 27, 222.

106. Brown, op.cit., p. 75, footnote number 127.

107. Raymond E. Brown, “The Resurrection and Biblical Criticism”, Commonweal, November 24, 1967, pp. 233, 235.

108. Bornkamm, op.cit., pp. 184-185.

109. McLeman, op.cit., pp. 212-213.

110. Schonfield, op.cit., p. 152.

111. Charles C. Anderson, Critical Quests of Jesus (Grand Rapids: William B, Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1969), pp. 55-57.

112. McNaugher, op.cit., p. 157.

113. Anderson, Critical Quests of Jesus, op.cit., pp. 5-56; Orr, op.cit., p. 235.

114. Ander2on, Ibid., p. 56; Orr, Ibid., p. 238; McNaugher, op.cit., p. 157.

115. Cf. for instance, Pfleiderer’s work The Early Christian Conception of Christ (London: Williams and Norgate, 1905), see pp. 63-83 for his account of some of the similarities between Jesus’ miracles and those found in other ancient relgions.

116. Otto Pfleiderer, Primitive Christianity, translated by W. Montgomery (Four volumes; Clifton: Reference Book Pubishers, 1965), see vol. I, pp. 1, 5, 23-25 for instance.

117. Orr, op.cit., pp. 235-261; McNaugher, op.cit., p. 157.

118. Pfleiderer, Primitive Christianity, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 5-6, 24-25; vol. II, 186, 371-372; vol. IV, p. 76. See also The Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., pp. 84-133.

119. Friedreich Ghillany was author nineteenth century scholar who likewise combined visions with legends which were influenced by myths from other ancient religions (Schweitzer, op.cit., pp/ 167, 170).

120. Pfleiderer, The Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., p. 157-158; Primitive Christianity, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 10-14; vol. II, pp. 115-116, 125.

121. For instance, Hooke favors the partial use of this view. See his work used above (op.cit., pp. 173-179).

122. Bultmann does not actually offer much rationalization for the resurrection. Neither does he appear very interested in developing theories as to why it did not occur. Therefore it is hard to “label” him at this point. However, he does believe that this occurrence is a myth, in some ways similar to other ancient myths, as will be perceived below. Because his treatment is nevertheless quite similar in several ways to these we have been discussing, we will include him here. The critique of this theory also applys to his views about this event.

123. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 10, footnote number two, and pp. 15-16.

124. Bultmann, “The Study of the Synoptic Gospels” in Form Criticism, op.cit., pp. 36-39.

125. See, for instance, Ibid., pp. 66, 72.

126. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 42.

127. Ibid., pp. 34, 38, 42.

128. Ibid., pp. 15-16; see also Bultmann’s History and Eschatology (New York: Harper and Row Publishers, 1962), p. 7.

129. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth. Ibid., p. 40 and Theology of the New Testament, op.cit., vol. I, p. 345; vol. II, p. 153.

130. Cf. the references in footnote 129 with History and Eschatology, op.cit., pp. 54-55.

131. Bultmann, Theology of the New Testament, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 31, 82.

132. Bultmann, “The Study of the Synoptic Gospels” in Form Criticism, op.cit., pp. 60-61.

133. Randall, op.cit., pp. 553-554; cf. p. 293.

134. Otto Pfleiderer, Philosophy and Development of Religion (Two volumes; Edinburgh: William Blackwood and Sons, 1894), vol. I, pp. 5-6.

135. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 4-5.

136. We note here once again that since the vision theory has been perceived above to be an inadequate explanation to account for the resurrection, we will not reopen the subject here even though both Pfleiderer and Bultmann seem to also prefer this theory along with the mythical or legendary theory.

137. Pfleiderer, Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., pp. 91-93.

138. Cf. Orr, op.cit., p. 237.

139. Hooke, op.cit., pp. 20-23.

140. Ibid., pp. 39-41.

141. Ibid., pp. 67-70.

142. Pfleirderer, Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., pp. 94-95; Orr, op.cit., p. 237; Yamauchi, op.cit., March 15, 1974, p. 4.

143. Pfleiderer, Ibid., p. 97.

144. Orr, op.cit., p. 235 and Pfleiderer, Primitive Christianity, vol. I, pp. 5, 23-25 for instance.

145. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 10; Marxsen, op.cit., p. 80. Even Bultmann recognizes this (Theology of the New Testament, op.cit., vol. I, p. 45).

146. See, for example, Marxsen, Ibid., pp. 52, 80; cf. p. 86; Brown The Viringal Concerption and Bodily Resurretion of Jesus, op.cit., p. 81; Reginald Fuller, Ibid., pp. 10-14, 28.

147. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 90.

148. Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., p. 81; Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 104-105.

149. Reginald Fuller, Ibid., Fuller lists some of these phraces with are foreign to Paul’s speech patterns in footnote number one, chapter two, p. 199.

150. For an evaluation of this conclusion see Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, p. 81, footnote number 140 and Reginald Fuller, Ibid., pp. 10-11.

151. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 10; Ladd, op.cit., p. 105.

152. Ibid., pp. 14, 28; Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., p. 92; Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 90; Ladd, op.cit., p. 105.

153. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 48-49, 70.

154. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 90.

155. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 48; Morrison, op.cit., p. 107.

156. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 91.

157. Orr, op.cit., p. 246.

158. J.N.D. Anderson, op.cit., pp. 90-91.

159. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 29-30; Marxsen, op.cit., p. 81.

160. It is not within the scope of this paper to thoroughly examine the question of the authorship of the four gospels. But suffice it to say that most critical scholars recognize at least some eyewitness testimony behind these four books. Matthew is often taken to be the author of the Q document and thus is an eyewitness testimony for one of the major sources of the first gospel. The author of the second gospel is usually asserted to be Joh Mark, who is believed to have recorded the testimony of Peter, another eyewitness and apostles. Most scholars believe that Luke is the author of the third gospel and the book of Acts, with many recognizing that Luke claims to have collected his information from eyewitnesses (Luke 1:1-4). Part of the reason for the new resurgence of interest in the authority of the fourth gospel is that it is often recognized that this book is very close to the eyewitness testimony of the apostles John. For these and similar conclusions, see Archibald M. Hunter, Introducing the New Testament (Second edition; Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1957), pp. 41-43, 49-50, 55-56, 61-63; Ladd, op.cit., pp. 74-78; Robert M. Grant, An Historical Introduction to the New Testament (London: Collins, 1963), pp. 119, 127-129, 134-135, 160; George A. Buttrick, editor The Interpreter’s Bible (Twelve volumes; New York and Nashville: Abingdon-Cokesbury Press, 1951-1956) vol. 7, p. 242 and vol. 8, pp. 9-10, 440-441; Raymond E. Brown, New Testament Essays (Milwaukee: The Bruce Publishing Company, 1965), pp. 129-131; William Hamilton, The Modern Reader’s Guide to John (New York: Association Press, 1959), pp. 13-15; Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 188-194.

161. See Fuller, Ibid., p. 48.

162. For the traditions concerning the martyr’s deaths suffered by all of the twelve apostles (except John) and other early prominent Christians like Mark and Luke, see Marie Gentert King, editor, Foxe’s Book of Martyrs (Westwood: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1968), pp. 11-13 for instance. Cf. also the witness of Eusebius’ (Grand Rapids: Baker Book House, 1969), pp. 58, 75-80.

163. J.N.D. Anderson, op.cit., p. 90.

164. Even Bultmann admits this, as we saw above (“New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit.,p .42). There is a difference between saying that the resurrection was a legend or myth and that it was fraud. The former, which is the theory we are discussing here, advocated that the disciples and other early Christians formulated the stories because they really believed Jesus was alive (such as the view of Pfleiderer and Bultmann). The second theory advocates that the disciples simply invented the story in spite of believing that Jesus was dead. Some still hold the former theory (legends or myths). But it is obvious why the latter (fraud) is rejected. The psychological improbabilities of someone dying only for a known fraud, as well as the other reasons against this theory as listed above, therefore make it impossible.

165. This theory usually referred to as the “fraud theory”, is not held today among theologians to the knowledge of this writer. This is because of the reasons given above. This also includes theories of the disciples stealing the dead body of Christ, for this would again involve their lying about the appearances when they would have known that Jesus was not alive. Men do not die for a known lie. For these and the other objections already given, this expansion of the fraud theory is also unanimously rejected.

166. This point is admitted by both Pfleiderer (The Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., pp. 157-58) and b Bultmann (“New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 34).

167. Orr, op.cit., p. 236; Pfleiderer, Ibid., p. 102.

168. Orr, op.cit., p. 246; McNaugher, op.cit., p. 157.

169. Orr, Ibid., p. 236.

170. Ibid., p. 247, footnote number one.

171. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p .91.

172. Lewis, Miracles, op.cit., pp. 117-118, 120.

173. Orr, op.cit., pp. 249-250.

174. Plfeiderer, The Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., pp. 153-154, 159.

175. Ibid., pp. 154-155; cf. p. 103.

176. Ibid., p. 94.

177. Ibid., p. 103; cf. p. 155; Orr, op.cit., p. 252.

178. Hooke, op.cit., pp. 21-22; Yamauchi, op.cit., March 15, 1974, 1974, p. 4.

179. Hooke, Ibid., p. 40; Pfleiderer, The Early Christian Conception of Christ, op.cit., p. 99.

180. Yamauchi, op.cit., March 15, 1974, p. 4: Orr, op.cit., p. 250.

181. Yamauchi, Ibid., p. 5. See also J.N.D. Anderson, Christianity and Comparative Religion (Downers Grove: Inter-Varsity Press, 1974), P. 39.

182. Yamauchi, Ibid,; Anderson, Ibid., p. 38.

183. Orr, op.cit., pp. 242-243, 251.

184. See, for instance, Ibid., p. 257.

185. Yamauchi, op.cit., March 15, 1974, p. 5. Cf. Hooke, op.cit., p. 68.

186. Orr, op.cit., pp. 247, 256-257. Cf. also Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 91. For some of the general disbelief in the Jedaeo-Christian concept of resurrection, note the Hebrew and Greek responses to the idea in Mk. 12:18; Acts 17:31-32; 26:8.

187. Other reasons could also be given against the legendary or mythical theory. For instance, we are left without any adequate explantion for the beginnings of the church or for the belief in the empty tomb if this theory were correct. This writer has formulated a list of 33 total reasons (revolving around points such as those enumerated in the four major criticisms above) for rejecting this theory.

188. Orr, op.cit., pp. 245-246, 253.

189. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 4-5 for instance.

190. Schaaffs often directs his attacks specifically at Bultmann for using an outdated scientific world view, a criticism which nullifies Bultmann’s rejection of the miraculous. It is not possible to handle miracles in such a way, as if they were strictly impossible from the start. See Schaaffs, op.cit., pp. 13, 15, 24-25, 31, 60, 64.

191. Clark also realizes that Bultmann’s defective scientific understanding cannot be used to rule out miracles today. See Clark, “Bultmann’s Three Storied Universe” in Gawbelein, op.cit., pp. 218-219.

192. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 38 for example.

193. Macquarrie, op.cit., pp. 185-186.

194. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 42.

195. Ibid.

196. Brown, “The Resurrection and Biblical Criticism”, op.cit., p. 233.

197. Bornkamm, op.cit., p. 185.

198. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit

Chapter 7

1. For the relation between Barth and the nineteenth century liberal theology which his thought was to replace, see the brief summation in Chapter Six, footnote number one. Barth’s neo-orthodox theology as a whole was indebted to Kierkegaard for much of its framework and foundation, and for many of its key facets. See, for instance, Bernard Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1966), pp. 89-92.

2. See Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 80-84; cf. Ramm, Ibid., pp. 74-76, 79-80, 89-92. I the next chapter we will discuss some of these theologians who were influenced by Kierkegaard in their acceptance of the resurrection with the stipulation that it cannot be demonstrated.

3. See, for example, Rudolf Bultmann, Jesus Christ and Mythology (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1958), pp. 61-62, 71-72, 80, 84.

4. Martin J. Heinecken, “Soren Kierkegaard”, in A Handbook of Christian Theologians, edited by Martin C. Marty and Dean G. Peerman (Cleveland: The World Publishing Company, 1965), pp. 125-126.

5. Soren Kierkegaard, The Point of View for My Work as an Author, edited by Benjamin Nelson, translated by Walter Lowrie (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1962) pp. 76-80. Cf. also Heinecken, Ibid., p. 125.

6. Kierkegaard, Ibid., see Appendix A, written by the translator, pp. 162-163; Heinecken, Ibid., pp. 126-127.

7. Kierkegaard, Ibid., see Appendix B, written by the translator, pp. 163-165; cf. Kierkegaard’s own assessment, pp. 94-95. Cf. also Heinecken, Ibid., p. 128.

8. Kierkegaard’s polemic against the “Christianity” of his day is especially strong in his work attack Upon Christendom, translated by Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1972). For his evaluation of Danish Christianity such as spoken of here, compare pp. 132-133, 139, 145, 149, 164-165 for instance, or see the essay “What Christ’s Judgment is About Official Christianity”, Ibid., pp. 117-124. For belief discussion of Kierkegaard’s attack against the influence of Hegelianism upon Danish Christianity as mentioned above, see also Heinecken, Ibid., pp. 127-128, 134-135.

9. For Kierkegaard’s own evaluation of what a real Christian is, including these points just mentioned, see Ibid., pp. 23, 149, 210, 213, 221, 268, 280, 287, 290 or example. Heinecken agrees with this summary, Ibid., pp. 131, 134.

10. Heinecken, Ibid., p. 127.

11. This work is translated by David Swenson (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974).

12. This work is also translated by David Swenson (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974).

13. Kierkegaard, The Point of View for My Work as an Author, op.cit., pp. 13-14, 53, 97.

14. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., pp. 86-97, 115-343 for example.

15. Ibid., p. 323. For instance, see Philosophical Fragments, op.cit., pp. 93-110. For the importance of these two texts as the writings of Kierkegaard which most influenced contemporary theology and philosophy, see Heinecken’s “Soren Kierkegaard”, in Marty and Peerman, op.cit., pp. 131-132.

16. Runes, op.cit., p. 160.

17. In addition to the references listed above, see James Collins, “Faith and Reflection in Kierkegaard” in A Kierkegaard Critique, edited by Howard A. Johnson and Niels Thulstrup (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1962), pp. 141-142, 147-148. Cf. Lev Shestov, Athens and Jerusalem, translated by Bernard Martin (No city: Ohio University Press, 1966), p. 242.

18. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 80-81, 84; Heinecken, “Soren Kierkegaard”, Marty and Peerman, op.cit., pp. 127, 142. Cf. Runes, op.cit., p. 124.

19. See, for example, Wesley Barnes, The Philosophy and Lierature of Existentialism, op.cit., pp. 46-47.

20. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., title of Part Two, Chapter II, p. 169.

21. Ibid., p. 173.

22. Ibid., p.. 173-174.

23. Ibid., p. 174.

24. Ibid., pp. 115, 177-178.

25. Ibid., p. 176 and Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., p. 97.

26. Kierkegaard, Ibid., pp. 117-118, 178-179.

27. Ibid., p. 178 and Kierkegaard's Philosophical Fragments, op.cit., pp. 55-57.

28. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, Ibid., pp. 42, 116.

29. Ibid., p. 178 and Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments, op.cit., pp. 49, 55; cf. Robert L . Perkins, Soren Kiekegaard (Richmond: John Knox Press, 1969), p. 17.

30. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, Ibid., pp. 86-97. See also James Brown, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Buber and Barth (New York: Collins Books, 1967), pp. 57-60.

31. Gotthold E. Lessing, Lessing’s Theological Writings, edited by Henry Chadwick (London: A. and C. Black Ltd., 1956), p. 53.

32. Ibid., pp. 53-55.

33. Ibid., p. 55.

34. Ibid., this essay about Reimarus appears on pp. 9-29. Cf. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 32.

35. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., p. 88. Cf. Fuller, Ibid., pp. 34-35.

36. Lessing, op.cit., p. 53; cf. p. 54. See Fuller, Ibid, p. 34.

37. Immanuel Kant, Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, translated by Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt H, Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1960), pp. 58-59, note. Cf. Fuller, Ibid., p. 37.

38. Kant, Ibid., p. 119, note. Cf. Fuller, Ibid., pp. 37-38.

39. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., p. 89; cf. p. 47.

40. See Ibid., pp. 38, 89, 190 and Kierkegaard’s Philosophy Fragments, op.cit., pp. 108-109 for instance. See footnote number 46 below.

41. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, Ibid., p. 33, 42, 45. On Kierkegaard’s belief that history is an objective approach, compare Ibid., p. 173 for instance, in addition to the discussion above.

42. Ibid., pp. 188, 194. See also Heinecken, “Soren Kierkegaard”, in Marty and Peerman, op.cit., p. 131; cf. p. 138 and Brown, op.cit., p. 59.

43. Kierkegaard, Ibid., pp. 189-190; cf. p. 30. Cf. Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., pp. 7, 94-95.

44. Kierkegaard, Ibid., pp. 42-43 and Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments, op.cit., p. 108. Cf. Brown, op.cit., p. 59.

45. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, Ibid., pp. 46-47.

46. See Brown, op.cit., pp. 57-59; Perkins, op.cit., p. 17; Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., p. 79 and Schaeffer, The God Who is There, op.cit., p. 21. Kierkegaard does not accept this idea exactly as it appears in Lessing, however. For Lessing the leap is made by persons who are removed from the historical events by time (perhaps by hundred of years), but who still wish to exercise faith. The leap from history to faith would not be needed if we had all been contemporaries of the event in question. But for Kierkegaard, the leap from historical events in the life of Jesus to faith in these events must be made by all believers because there is no benefit in being a contemporary (see Kierkegaard, Ibid., p. 89; cf. Brown, Ibid., pp. 58-59).

47. Kierkegaard, Philosophical Fragments, op.cit., p. 53.

48. Ibid.

49. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., p. 306.

50. Ibid., pp. 51, 117, 177.

51. Ibid., pp. 42, 116.

52. Kierkegaard, Philosophical Fragments, op.cit., pp. 53, 55, 57.

53. Ibid., pp. 53-55 and Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., pp. 118, 209 for instance.

54. To be sure, Kierkegaard did not assert that there were no objective truths. He did allow for such. However, objective approaches simply cannot lead to eternal truth and neither can the objective be the basis for faith. See Heinecken’s “Soren Kierkegaard”, in Marty and Peerman, op.cit., pp. 139-141.

55. We also found scholarly support of this definition as well, so as not to attempt to settle such philosophical issues simply by referring to definitions.

56. For Kierkegaard’s use of logic and reason in his polemic, see Heinecken's “Soren Kierkegaard” in Marty and Peerman, op.cit., p. 132; cf. pp. 127-128.

57. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., p. 89. See also Brown, op.cit., pp. 38-39 and Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 34-35.

58. For this definition of faith by Kierkegaard, see his Attack Upon “Christendom”, op.cit., pp. 149, 210, 213, 221, 280, 287, for instance, See especially Heinecken, “Soren Kierkegaard” in Marty and Peerman, op.cit., pp. 131, 133, 134, 138 for the same summary.

Chapter 8

1 . See the introduction to Kierkegaard in chapter seven for many of these details. Cf. also Heinecken, “Soren Kierkegaard”, in Marty and Peerman, Ibid., p. 136.

2. Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., pp. 74-76, 79-80, 89-92.

3. Karl Barth, Anselm: Fides Quaerens Intellectum, translated by Ian W. Robertson (Richmond John Knox Press, 1960).

4. Ibid., pp. 39-40, 101, 151.

5. Ibid., pp. 18-20, 80, 86, 128, 152.

6. See Hans Urs van Balthasar, The Theology of Karl Barth, translated by John Drury (New York: Holt, Rinehard and Windton, 1971), p. 148 and Herbert Hartwell, The Theology of Karl Barth (London: Gerald Duckworth and Company, Ltf., 1964), pp. 49, 56, 184.

7. Barth, Anselm, op.cit., pp. 18-20, 128, 39-40; cf. von Balthasar, Ibid., p. 128.

8. Among other facets, neo-orthodox theology (also termed dialectical theology) affirms that there is a vast guld between God and man. As a result, there exists a tension between the things of God and the things of man. An answer of both “Yes” and “No” is therefore given by these theologians to certain questions pertaining to this relationship. A possible example of such a seemingly contradictory position is that the Bible if both the Work of God and the word of man. Thus one might answer both “Yes” and “No” to the question of whether the Bible is the work of human writer. See Ramm, A Handbook to Contemporary Theology, op.cit., pp. 35-36.

9. Barth, The Epistle to the Romans, op.cit., p. 30.

10. See penetrating analysis by Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 82-84.

11. Barth, The Epistle to the Romans, op.cit., p. 204.

12. Ibid., p. 203.

13. Ibid., cf. pp. 30, 195, 203.

14. Karl Barth, The Word of God and the Word of Man, translated by Douglas Horton (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1957), p. 89. The essays in this book at dated 1916-1923.

15. Ibid., p. 90.

16. Ibid., p. 91.

17. Ibid., p. 92; cf. p. 120.

18. Karl Barth, The Resurrection of the Dead, translated by H. J. Stenning (New York: Fleming K. Revell Company, 1933).

19. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 89-90.

20. Barth, The Resurrection of the Dead, op.cit., pp. 134, 138, 139.

21. Ibid., pp. 135-138.

22. Carl F.H. Henry, editor, Jesus of Nazareth: Saviour and Lord (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1966), p. 11.

23. Karl Barth, Theology and Church: Shorter Writings 1920-1928, translated by Louise Pettibone Smith (New York: Harper and Row, Publisher, 1862), p. 62.

24. See Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 111-112; cf. p. 115 and Charles C. Anderson, The Historical Jesus: A Continuing Quest., p. 157, footnote number 3 for instance. We will return later to Barth’s conception of the resurrection as having occurred in a history different from that of other events.

25. Concerning Barth’s earlier primary interest in dialectics and his later primary interest in the analogy of faith, see von Balthasar, op.cit., pp. 78-80, 90, 92-93.

26. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 147-148.

27. This greater emphasis on the reality of Jesus' resurrection is especially perceptible in Barth’s Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 302, 309, 318, 336-337, 351-352, for instance. See also Barth’s Dogmatics in Outline, translated by G.T. Thompson (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1959), pp. 122-123. Cf. Hartwell, op.cit., pp. 122-123.

28. Karl Barth, How I Changed My Mind (Richmond: John Knox Press, 1966), see p. 69 for an example for his attitude.

29. Karl Barth, The Faith of the Church, edited by Jean-Louis Leuba, translated by Gabriel Vahanian (New York: Meridian Books, Inc., 1958), pp. 96-99.

30. Barth, Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, p. 335.

31. Ibid., p. 334.

32. Ibid., p. 336.

33. Ibid., pp. 300-301.

34. Ibid., p. 336; cf. Barth’s The Faith of the Church, op.cit., p. 99.

35. Ibid., especially p. 335; see also pp. 300, 341.

36. Cf. Barth’s work The Resurrection of the Dead, op.cit., p. 135 with Ibid., p. 335.

37. Indeed, in The Faith of the Church, Barth notes that he is utilizing a different definition of history when he affirms that events such as the resurrection occurred (op.cit., pp. 98-99).

38. Barth, Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 336-337, 351-352.

39. More will be said about this criticism later.

40. See especially Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript, op.cit., pp. 188-190 and the discussion above on Kierkegaard. Cf. Brown, op.cit., p. 59.

41. Cf. Barth’s The Word of God and the Word of Man, op.cit., p. 90.

42. Barth, Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 300-301, 334, 336.

43. Barth uses these descriptive words to refer to his concept of redemptive or spiritual history. See Ibid., p. 336 and The Resurrection of the Dead, op.cit., pp. 134, 139.

44. Wand, op.cit., p. 23.

45. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 99.

46. History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 87-88.

47. Ibid., cf. also pp. 106-107.

48. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 111-112; cf. p. 115.

49. In addition to those listed above, see, for instance, Henry, op.cit., pp. 11-12 and Henry’s own comments in the debate on the resurrection (he was a participant) recorded in the appendix of Montgomery’s History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 85, 96, 105. The contradictory aspect of Barth’s concept was also confirmed by Clark Pinnock in personal correspondence with this writer, dated July 19, 1971. See also Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 82-84; cf. pp. 69, 71. Charles Anderson, in The Historical Jesus: A Continuing Quest, op.cit., pp. 157-158, footnote number three and Ramm, in A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., p. 90, also note Barth’s position.

50. For example, see especially Barth’s Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, p. 335.

51. Montgomery, History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 99-101, 106-107.

52. Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., p. 90.

53. Barth, Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, p. 336; cf. p. 334.

54. Ibid., pp. 248-254 for instance. See Ramm, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., pp. 16, 108.

55. See Henry, Jesus of Nazareth: Saviour and Lord, op.cit., p. 10 where this criticism is also developed.

56. This tendency to believe that the New Testament never intends to demonstrate that the resurrection really did happen is evidence in both the early and in the late Barth. See his earlier work The Resurrection of the Dead, op.cit., pp. 131-138 and his later opus Church Dogmatics, op. cit., vol. IV, part 1, p. 335.

57. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 39.

58. Bultmann, Theology of the New Testament, vol. I, p. 82.

59. See Barth’s Church Dogmatics, vol. IV, part I, pp. 334-336.

60. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 39.

61. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 29.

62. Besides this portion and I Cor. 15:4-8, see such passages as Matt. 28:8-9; Jn. 20:17 (in the Greek); 20:19-31; Acts 10:39-41.

63. Bultmann also believes that the gospels and Paul endeavor to prove that Jesus had appeared to the apostles. He likewise recognizes that I Cor. 15:3-8 and Luke 24:39-43 are good example of this tendency. See “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 39.

64. See W.E. Vine, An Expository Dictionary of New Testament Words, (Four volumes in one; Old Tappan: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1966), volume III, pp. 220-221. See also Robertson, op.cit., vol. III, p. 6.

65. This is admitted by both Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 39 and by Marxsen, op.cit., p. 169. Marxsen note that the preaching of repentance and belief in the Lordship of Jesus are both based on the proof that Jesus rose from the dead, according to these verses.

66. See Bultmann, Theology of the New Testament, op.cit., vol. I, p. 27.

67. These four criticisms will be briefly summarized at the conclusion to the next section.

68. Emil Brunner, The Christian Doctrine of Creation and Redemption, volume II of Dogmatics, translated by Olive Wyon (Three volumes; Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1952) p. 336. See also Brunner's work The Mediator, translated by Olive Wyon (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, p. 153.

69. Brunner, The Mediator, Ibid., p. 573.

70. Brunner, Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. II, p. 369; cf. p. 153.

71. Ibid, pp. 366-372; cf. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 155-156.

72. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Christ the Center, translated by John Bowden (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966), p. 76.

73. Ibid., pp. 74-77.

74. Ronald J. Stone, Reinhold Niebuhr: Prophet to Politicians (Nashville; Abingdon Press, 1972), pp. 22-23, 52.

75. Reinhold Niebuhr, Faith and History (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1949), p. 147.

76. Bornkamm, op.cit., pp. 180, 183-184.

77. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 23, 48, 81.

78. See Daniel Fuller’s treatment of Grass’ position for additional criticisms of it (op.cit., pp. 150-156).

79. Jurgen Moltmann, Theology of Hope, translated by James W. Leitch (New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1967), pp. 165-202. See especially pp. 165, 172, 174, 177, 188-189, 197. Cf. Nelson R. Chamberlain, “Jurgen Moltmann: Apostle of Christian Hope?”, Christianity Today, June 21, 1974, pp. 7, 8.

80. Moltmann, Ibid., see especially pp. 178-182, 190, 202.

81. Ibid., p. 176.

82. Jurgen Moltmann, Religion, Revolution and the Future, translated by M. Douglas Meeks (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1969), especially pp. 50-51.

83. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, op.cit., pp. 177-182, 190, 197. Cf. Robert J. Blaikie, ”Secular Christianity” and God Who Acts (Grand Rapids: William R. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1970), pp. 129-134. See the next chapter on Pannenberg for a critique of a position somewhat similar to Moltmann’s, one which also gives the future the place of priority. Many of the criticism offered in the next chapter also apply to Moltmann.

84. Berger, op.cit., pp. 39-40.

85. Ram, A Handbook of Contemporary Theology, op.cit., pp. 90, 108.

86. Barth, Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 248-254 for example.

Chapter 9

1. When it is asserted that this event can be demonstrated, reference is being made to probabilities. These scholars hold that this event can be demonstrated to a high probability by a reasonable approach to the Christian faith which includes a historical examination of the known facts.

2. See editor Richard John Neuhaus’ introductory essay “Wolfhart Pannenberg: Profile of a Theologian” in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1969), pp. 9-50. See especially pp. 10-11 for this statement.

3. Pannenberg, Revelation As History, op.cit., pp. 142-144 for instance.

4. See this proclivity in such scholars as Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 144; Montgomery, History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 72-80; McNaugher, op.cit., pp. 144-185 and Smith, op.cit., pp. 167-228.

5. Editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 9.

6. Ibid., pp. 10, 17.

7. For instance, M. Douglas Meeks deals primarily with Moltmann in his work Origins of the Theology of Hope (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1974). See p. 2 for his conviction that others like Pannenberg and Metz cannot be connected completely with Moltmann.

8. This work was edited by Pannenberg and published in English under the title Revelation as History, translated by David Granskou (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1968).

9. See editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 16 and Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 178.

10. Neuhaus, Ibid., p. 11.

11. Ibid., p. 15.

12. Ibid., p. 30 See the treatment of Barth above, including Pannenberg’s view. See also Pannenberg’s Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 99; cf. his Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 9-10. More will be said later concerning his view of the resurrection as a demonstrable event.

13. Neuhaus, Ibid., p. 37 and Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 178.

14. See Meeks, op.cit., p. 10.

15. Brian O. McDermott, S.J., “Pannenberg’s Resurrection Christology: A Critique”, Theological Studies, Volume 35, number 4, December, 1974, pp. 711-721. See also Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 53.

16. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 51-53, 73.

17. Ibid., pp. 56, 62, 111-112.

18. Ibid., pp. 62-63, 71.

19. Ibid., pp. 68, 70-71.

20. Ibid., pp. 76-77, 82.

21. Ibid., p. 70.

22. Editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 42.

23. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 133-135, 142-143; see McDermott, op.cit., p. 714.

24. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 127; see McDermott, Ibid., p. 711; 715-717.

25. Editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 25; cf. p. 42.

26. See Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 139 for instance Neuhaus, Ibid., p. 41.

27. Pannenberg, Revelation as History., pp. 125-131.

28. Ibid., p. 3-13.

29. Ibid., pp. 125-127; cf. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 182 and Blaikie, op.cit., pp. 156, 162.

30. See Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 19.

31. Ibid., pp. 7, 16; cf. Blaikie, op.cit., pp. 156-158, 162.

32. Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 16, 19. For instance, Schleiermacher’s view is that all events, even the most mundane ones, are miracles. It is not simply the strange or unexplained event alone which is Supernatural. See the discussion of Schleiermacher’s view of miracles above. See above also Schleiermacher’s work On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers, op.cit., pp. 88-89, 113-114, explanation number 16 for instance.

33. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 131-135.

34. The logic of this assertion will be challenged below.

35. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 132-134.

36. Ibid., p. 127; see also Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., pp. 62-63, 68, 70-71.

37. Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, Ibid., pp. 54, 63, 70.

38. Neuhaus in Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 42.

39. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 141-143. See McDermott, op.cit., pp. 713-714.

40. Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 134 and Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 62.

41. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, Ibid., pp. 135-139.

42. Ibid., pp. 135-137.

43. Ibid., p. 137.

44. Ibid., pp. 138-139.

45. Cf. Pannenberg’s Jesus—God and Man., p. 99 with editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., pp. 20, 38, 46.

46. See Neuhaus, Ibid., pp. 20-21 and Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 180-181 for some of Pannenberg’s techniques in investigating evidence.

47. Fuller, Ibid., p. 180.

48. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 139-145.

49. Ibid., pp. 139-141.

50. Ibid., pp. 141-143. On the universal aspect of the offer of the Kingdom, see Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., pp. 73, 76, 85, 88 for example.

51. Editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, Ibid., p. 41; cf. p. 10. For the apostle Paul’s stance, see I Cor. 15:13-19.

52. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 137; cf. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 181-182.

53. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man., op.cit., pp. 95-97.

54. Ibid., pp. 90-91.

55. See Ibid., p. 99 and Pannenberg’s Basic Questions in Theology,, Ibid., vol. I, pp. 15-16. Cf. editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 30 and Blaikie, op.cit., pp. 156, 206.

56. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 145-148.

57. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 145-148.

58. Ibid., p. 145.

59. Ibid., p. 146.

60. Ibid., pp. 149-152.

61. Ibid., pp. 149-150.

62. Ibid., pp. 150-151.

63. Ibid., pp. 152-155.

64. Ibid., see pp. 10-12.

65. Ibid., pp. 153-155.

66. Ibid.

67. Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, op. cit., pp. 56, 68.

68. See Ibid., pp. 50, 53, 73, 81, 133.

69. In the use of the New Testament Scriptures which are to follow, the issue is not to defend these words and argue if they were actually spoken by Jesus or not. Rather, we are primarily concerned at this point with what the Scriptures teach about the nature and existence of God, not about who said which words.

70. Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 56.

71. For Pannenberg’s connection of these idea with Jesus’ teachings, see Ibid., p. 56. But he strangely gives no references for these assertions.

72. For Pannenberg’s assertions against he “direct” views of inspiration see Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 9-13, 152. For his own view see pp. 125ff.

73. For example, see Ladd, op.cit., pp. 17, 144; cf. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 186, 230, 237; cf. p. 234. At this point, Pannenberg's contention of revelation in history in correct.

74. There is no attempt here to employ any kind of circular reasoning concerning the inspiration of Scripture by first asking what the self-witness of the Scriptures is and then assuming that this is true. This would not be a correct procedure. IT is not our purpose here to even discuss whether this self-witness to inspiration is valid. Rather, the concern is that Pannenberg does not accept the New Testament’s claim to revelation in the Scriptures because of what he feels is the influence of gnosticism (see Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 10-12, 152). It is this claim which must be examined, especially as regards the clearly non-gnostic portions of Scripture. This examination is very important, since Pannenberg is interested in developing an understanding of what the Jewish conception of revelation consisted. This will be our endeavor here as well.

75. Ibid., pp. 152-155.

76. Cf. for example Num. 22:38, 23:12, 16, 26: Jer. 1:6-9, 26:2; Ezek. 3:10-11.

77. One such instance is Jer. 15:19-21.

78. See G. Ernest Wright’s exegesis of “The Book of Numbers” in The Interpreter’s Bible, edited by George Arthur Buttrick, op.cit., vol. II, pp. 450-451.

79. A general reference to the written words of the prophets occurs in Zech. 7:12. The words here would probably be the written ones, since the reference is to prophets of former times whose writings were in existence.

80. Moses is referred to as a prophet in Duet. 34:10.

81. See Ex. 17:24; 24:4; 34:27-28; Deut. 31:9, 24-26.

82. As with the other Old Testament verses listed in this section, it is not our purpose here to debate who is the author of these words. It is rather our concern to ascertain what the Jewish view of revelation was, especially as spoken and written by chosen men of God. These verses are therefore very valuable in reflecting this belief.

83. Cf. Mk. 12:36; Matt. 22:43-46; Luke 20:42 with II Sam. 23:2. One cannot object to the use of the New Testament verses here, because the Old Testament verse also confirms that the Lord spoke through David. Both express the direct revelation of God to him.

84. Rolf Rendtorff, in his essay, “The Concept of Revelation in Ancient Israel” (in Pannenberg’s Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 46-47), also recognizes a close relationship between word and revelation. However, like Pannenberg, he insists that the word is not really revelation. His view likewise falls prey to the same criticisms raised here. For instance, he must have received such word from the Lord. This is the whole point of Deut. 18:20-22. This word is God’s revealing the future through the prophet before the event in history occurs. Pannenberg especially misses this point in his exposition of the similarities between word and revelation (Ibid., 152-155). Without such revelation through the prophet there would be no foretelling of the event.

85. Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 12; cf. p. 152.

86. Rendtorff in Pannenberg, Ibid., p. 46.

87. Many scholars also believe that the Biblical witness provides written revelation of God. For this view see, for instance, Norwegian theologian Sigmund Mowinckel’s work The Old Testament as Word of God, translated by Reidar B. Bjornard (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1959), pp. 10-12, 23-26. See also Charles C. Anderson, The Historical Jesus: A Continuing Quest, op.cit., pp. 9-51 and Bernard Ramm, Protestant Christian Evidences, op.cit., pp. 224-249.

88. To be sure, there are some strong, carefully reasoned points in Pannenberg’s work. The strongest part of his theology will be discussed later.

89. McDermott, op.cit., p. 714.

90. Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p 59.

91. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 131.

92. As we have already noted, many would perhaps be more willing to grant that one of God’s methods of revelation is His acting in history, in addition to other modes of revelation. See Ladd, op.cit., pp. 17, 144; Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 186, 237.

93. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., pp. 142, 143.

94. Ibid., pp. 17-19.

95. Ibid., p. 16; cf. p. 7.

96. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 184-186.

97. See Blaikie, op.cit., p. 159.

98. See editor Neuhaus in Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., p. 42.

99. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., pp. 92-93.

100. Ibid., pp. 93-95.

101. Ibid., pp. 95-97.

102. Ibid., pp. 98-99, 105.

103. Ibid., p. 92.

104. The key passages teaching the objective nature of Jesus’ appearances include such portions as Matt. 28:9; Luke 24:36-43; John 20:17 (in the Greek); 20:20, 26-29; Acts 1:3.

105. For instance, the gospels assert that Jesus was already gone from the grave before the stone was rolled away, implying that he evacuated be means other than the doorway (Matt. 28:2-6). It is also reported that Jesus left the graveclothes behind, undisturbed, showing that he passed through them rather than having to unravel them (John 20:6-9; cf. Luke 24:12). He was also able to appear and disappear at will, even into locked rooms (Luke 24:30-31, 36; John 20:19, 26). See Ladd, op.cit., pp. 84-96, 126.

106. See especially I Cor. 15:42-50.

107. For instance, see Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 92; Ladd, op.cit., pp. 111, 114-118; Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., pp. 85-89 and Brown’s “The Resurrection and Biblical Criticism”, op.cit., p. 236; Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 179. See footnote number 113 below for others who also recognize this.

108. William Hallock Johnson, “The Keystone of the Arch”, Theology Today, edited by John A. MacKay, Number 1, April, 1949-January 1950, p. 20.

109. See I Cor. 15:3-4. For the reality of the empty tomb, see Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., pp. 100-104; Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 69-70, 179; Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., p. 122, footnote number 204 and p. 126; see also Brown’s article “The Resurrection and Biblical Criticism”, op.cit., p. 235. For the view that Paul also implied the empty tomb in I Cor. 15:4, see Reginald Fuller, Ibid., pp. 48-49, 69; Ramsey, op.cit., p. 44. In addition, see Robert M. Grant, A Historical Introduction to the New Testament, op.cit., p. 369 and Clark H. Pinnock, “On the Third Day” in Henry, op.cit., p. 15.

110. Cf. Ladd, op.cit., p. 105; see also p. 138 and Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., p. 91.

111. Ladd, Ibid., pp. 126, 138-139.

112. Luke records the more objective appearances to the disciples (see Luke 24:36-43; Acts 1:3; 10:40-41) right along with the three passage which narrate Paul’s conversion (Acts 9:1-9; 22:6-11; 26:12-18).

113. See Ladd, op.cit., pp. 126, 137-138; Brown, “The Resurrection and Biblical Criticism”, op.cit., p. 236; cf. Grant, Miracles and Natural Law, op.cit., pp. 229-230; see also Charles C. Anderson, The Historical Jesus: A Continuing Quest, op.cit., pp. 164-165; Smith, op.cit., pp. 194-195.

114. There are other substantial criticisms of Pannenberg’s thought which have not been mentioned here. For instance, Neuhaus has pointed out that Pannenberg’s concept of Kingdom of God as a possibility to be worked for in human society is perilously close to some of the ideas of the social gospel movement of the nineteenth century. The view that the Kingdom of God could become established in the social order through the effort of men failed. See Neuhaus in Pannenberg’s Theology and the Kingdom of God, op.cit., pp. 31-33. Cf. Pannenberg, Ibid., pp. 77, 79, 80, 84.

115. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., p. 88-106.

116. Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 147.

117. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., see the conclusion on p. 105.

118. Even those who do not accept Pannenberg’s view of the resurrection find his defense of this event to be quite sophisticated. See for instance, Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 22-23.

Chapter 10

1. The word “demonstrated”, once again, is not used here in the sense of absolute proof, but rather as it is related to probabilities. Thus, this section deals with the conviction that the factual evidence is such that the resurrection of Jesus is the most probable conclusion.

2. Daniel Fuller, op.cit. The examination of these various schools of thought and the subsequent evaluation of these three positions with regard to history is found on pp. 27-187.

3. Preliminary questions such as the authorship and date for Luke-Acts and discussed by Fuller, Ibid., pp. 190-199.

4. Ibid., pp. 199-208.

5. Ibid., pp. 208-229.

6. Ibid., pp. 188-190.

7. Ibid., pp. 190-191, 220.

8. Luke-Acts is addressed to Theophilus in particular (Luke 1:3; Acts 1:1), but there may have been other indirect recipients as well.

9. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 189-190, 223 for instance.

10. Ibid., pp. 223-225, 229, 235.

11. Ibid., se especially pp. 217, 219, 226,

12. Commands such as those recorded in Luke 24:47-48 and Acts 1:8.

13. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., see for example, pp. 223, 226-229, 246-247.

14. Ibid., p. 220.

15. Ibid., see especially pp. 190, 223, 235.

16. Ibid., pp. 242, 245.

17. For instance, se Fuller’s discussion an refutation of Paulus’ swoon theory (Ibid., pp. 38-39), Lessing’s and Kierkegaard’s attempts to remove the event from all verification (Ibid., pp. 35, 255-256) and Barth’s modification of this approach (Ibid., pp. 83-84, 88-90, 155-156). Luke’s proofs for the resurrection also serve as a refutation of Strauss’ vision theory (Ibid., cf. 45-49 with pp. 231-232).

18. Ibid., pp. 231-232.

19. Ibid., pp. 247-250.

20. Ibid., pp. 252-261. See especially pp. 252-253.

21. Ibid., especially pp. 255-259. See also pp. 220, 231-232.

22. Ibid., pp. 242, 245.

23. See Ladd’s book, I Believe in the Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit.

24. Ibid., pp. 12-13; cf. p. 23.

25. Ibid., p. 13-14. Concerning the need specifically to examine the resurrection, see p.. 27-28, 132-133.

26. Ibid., pp. 21, 25.

27. Ibid., pp. 25, 132.

28. Ibid., cf. p. 27 with pp. 13, 27, 139-141. See footnote number one above.

29. Ibid., p. 20.

30. Ibid., pp. 13, 91-94. Ladd does not simply enumerate facts just because they are recorded in the New Testament. Rather, he lists those which are known to be historically plausible.

31. Ibid., see pp. 133-139, where Ladd discusses five major alternative theories concerning the resurrection.

32. Ibid., see especially p. 136.

33. Ibid., pp. 139-141.

34. Ibid., pp. 25, 58.

35. Ibid., pp. 21, 25, 132.

36. Ibid., pp. 101-102, 139-140.

37. Ibid., p. 140. It must be noted here that the objection against Ladd is not due to his position that the resurrection is primarily know by faith, per se. It has already been pointed out above (chapter four) that faith is more important than reason, and so any type of metahistory is to begin to remove it from certain types of reasonable verification. This is to be guarded against. The problem is therefore in Ladd’s tendencies to begin to remove the resurrection away from the grasp of history (see Ibid., pp. 101-102, 139-140).

38. Ibid., pp. 26-27, 29, 132-133.

39. Ibid., pp. 12, 27, 140. It will be recalled that Barth opposed all such historical investigation of the resurrection and other modes of interaction between history and faith. As an example, see Barth’s Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 335, 341.

40. Ladd, Ibid., pp. 27, 132-142. As mentioned above, Barth asserts that it makes no significant difference if the tomb was opened or closed. In fact, sometimes a naturalistic theory is preferable to one’s trying to treat the resurrection as actual, fully objective history. See Barth’s The Resurrection of the Dead, op.cit., pp. 135-138 and The Word of God and the Word of Man, op.cit., p. 90.

41. Ladd, Ibid., pp. 13, 27, 139-141. It is because of Ladd’s emphasis on the ability of the resurrection to be demonstrated as the only adequate solution and because of the efforts to refute other alternate theories that he is included in this section and not with Barth in the former section. Ladd’s entire emphasis on the ability of faith to be investigated and reinforced by positive findings was the deciding factor here.

42. See the discussion of Barth above. Compare his Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, p. 335.

43. This is Blaikie’s criticism of Ladd’s position, op.cit., pp. 128-129, 134.

44. Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 114-116. However, Montgomery does not seem to be aware of Ladd’s belief that investigation of the resurrection is still possible even if it can primarily be known only be faith.

45. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 252-261 in particular.

46. Lewis, Miracles, op.cit., see especially pp. 56-63.

47. Ladd, op.cit., pp. 12-13, 139-141.

48. It is actually difficult to ascertain how much Ladd does agree with Barth here. See indications of a partial acceptance of Barth’s understanding of the resurrection of Ladd, Ibid., p. 21, 15, 101-102, 140. See also Montgomery, Where is History Going?, op.cit., p. 115.

49. By historically verifiable we are referring to the approach to history which accepts the event which bet supports the known facts. To this Ladd, Pannenberg, Daniel Fuller and C.S. Lewis all agree. In chapters two and three of this work this same conclusion of ascertaining historical events was also found to be the correct procedure. But we are also speaking of the need to realize that God’s raising Jesus from the dead is therefore a theological and historical explanation of a historical event. Thus we must not resort to any type of metahistory to explain the resurrection. With this Ladd seems to disagree (Ibid., pp. 101-102, 139-140).

50. Maier’s chief work on the resurrection is his book, First Easter, op.cit. See also “The Empty Tomb as History” in Christianity Today, op.cit.

51. We have discussed above the position of theologian/historian John Warwick Montgomery and ancient historian Edwin Yamauchi, both of whom also believe that the resurrection can be demonstrated to have occurred.

52. Montgomery, for instance, more often combines history and theology, being quite adept in both disciplines.

53. Maier, First Easter, op.cit., p. 114.

54. Ibid., and Maier’s “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., pp. 4, 5.

55. See Tacitus, Annuals, 15:44.

56. Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., p. 4. J.N.D. Anderson concurs in this position, op.cit., p. 19.

57. See Josephus, Antiquities, 18. 3.

58. Maier, First Easter, op.cit., p. 114. Other scholars also agree that Josephus did write this portion of Jesus (or at least one very similar to it), except for several “Christian” words. This position is held for at least three major reasons. First, there is no textual evidence against this section in spite of various readings in other places. Second, there is very good manuscript evidence for these statements about Jesus and it is therefore difficult to ignore it. Third, this portion is written in Josephus’ own style of writing. It is thus a warranted conclusion that there are several good reasons for accepting at least that Josephus did write of Jesus, mentioning several facets of his career. It is also a justified conclusion to say that, in all probability, Josephus at least recorded the belief in the resurrection without actually acknowledging that he accepted such a fact. For these three reasons and the concluding facts given here, see, in addition to Maier, J.N.D. Anderson, op.cit., p. 20. See especially F.F. Bruce’s two works, Jesus and Christian Origins Outside the New Testament ( (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1974), pp. 32-41, especially pp. 36-41 and The New Testament Documents: Are They Reliable? (Fifth Revised Edition; Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1967), pp. 102-112. Bruce, the Manchester scholar of Biblical criticism, has done much work on Josephus’ reference to Jesus and come to a conclusion quite similar to Maier’s.

59. See Matt. 28:11-15 for this report. It has already been shown above that the theory of the stolen body (or other such fraud on the part of the disciples) fails miserably in its attempt to explain the resurrection of Jesus (see chapter 7, footnote numbers 163, 164 and the discussion corresponding to these remarks). Briefly, this theory ignores at least five key objections. First, men do not die willingly for what they know to be simply a falsehood. Second, the tremendous psychological transformation of the disciples from backward fishermen to bold preachers cannot be explained by any fraudulent action, or else there would not have been this change. Third and closely related, none of the disciples ever recanted even at the threat of losing his life. This was totally opposed to their actions before the resurrection, such as in fleeing when Jesus was taken captive and by Peter’s subsequent denials. Fourth, the quality of the ethical teachings promulgated by the disciples precludes such actions. Fifth, it is admitted by all that the disciples at least believed that Jesus had risen from the dead. They would of course not believed that this event had actually occurred if they were the ones who had perpetrated the fraud. For these reasons (see also footnote numbers 61 and 62 below), no reputable scholar holds this view today. There is little doubt that this is one of the weakest theories ever formulated against the resurrection, yet it was the one chosen by the early Jewish leaders.

60. Maier, op.cit., pp. 116-117.

61. Ibid., pp. 114-115. In addition to the point made here be Maier, it should also be noted that the behavior of the Jewish leader in Acts also constitutes another objection to the stolen body (fraud) theory. If the Jewish rulers really believed that the disciples stole the body, they would not simply have commanded the disciples not to preach about Jesus (such as Acts 4:18, 21; 5:28, 40), but they would have forced them to admit and recant of their actions.

62. Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., p. 5.

63. Ibid., p. 4.

64. Maier, First Easter, op.cit., pp. 119-120.

65. Ibid., pp. 115, 121-122; “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., p. 5.

66. Maier, First Easter, Ibid., pp. 105-113, 122; cf. also pp. 77-80 and “The Empty Tomb as History”, Ibid., p. 5.

67. Maier, First Easter, Ibid., pp. 94, 96.

68. Ibid., p. 105 and “The Empty Tomb as History” , op.cit., p. 5.

69. Maier, First Easter, Ibid., this conclusion is stated on p. 120.

70. Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., pp. 5-6.

71. Ibid., pp. 4-5 and First Easter, op.cit., pp. 120-122.

72. Maier, First Easter, Ibid., especially pp. 105-113, 120-122.

73. For a very positive review of Maier’s work First Easter and one which recognizes the excellent job done by Maier in his historical demonstration of Jesus’ resurrection, see Lawrence E. Martin, “The Risen Christ”, The Christian Century, May 16, 1973, p. 577.

Part 3

Chapter 11

1. Randall, op.cit., pp. 293, 553-554.

2. Smith, op.cit., pp. 142-143.

3. Montgomery, The Suicide of Christian Theology, op.cit., pp. 28, 37-38.

4. Strauss, The New Life of Jesus, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 199-201.

5. Schleiermacher, The Christian Faith, op.cit., see especially vol. I, pp. 179, 181, 183. Cf. also vol. I, pp. 71, 178-184; vol. II, pp. 448-449 and Schleiermacher’s On Religion: Speeches to its Cultured Despisers, op.cit., pp. 88-89, 113-114 note number 16.

6. Schweitzer, op.cit., pp. 51-53.

7. Ibid., p. 154.

8. Renan, Life of Jesus, op.cit., pp. 147-155.

9. Pfleiderer, The Philosophy and Development of Religion, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 5-6.

10. Harnack, What is Christianity?, op.cit., pp. 25-31.

11. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology”, in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 4-5.

12. Tillich, Systematic Theology, op.cit., vol. I, pp. 115-117.

13. Robinson, Honest to God, op.cit., pp. 11-18, 64-68.

14. This summary of the criticisms of Hume is necessarily a brief one and thus the logic for these four criticisms cannot be properly analyzed from this presentation. For a complete analysis of the reasoning behind these statements, see chapter five.

15. See the above references to these ten theologians for these beliefs (to varying extents) on the part of each of them. In order to ascertain how similar the beliefs of these theologians are to Hume’s stance against miracles, compare chapter five.

16. See footnote numbers one through three above and the corresponding discussion.

17. J. Gresham Machen, Christianity and Liberalism (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdman’s Publishing Company, 1923), pp. 107-109.

18. The major theories advanced to explain the resurrection have been discussed earlier. It was found that formulations based upon a swoon, subjective or objective visions (including the “telegram theory” and ideas of the continuing spiritual presence of Jesus’ personality in the minds of the disciples), the influence of other ancient myths, the growth of legends or fraud (including the stolen body theory) all failed to account for the known facts. See especially chapter six above.

19. See the conclusions against each of these theories, especially in chapter six. Cf. for example, Maier, First Easter, op.cit., p. 113 and Ladd, op.cit., pp. 139-141.

20. See the discussion of these facets in chapter six above.

21. Admittedly, no one is able to convince everyone that his view is right. However, if there was a naturalistic theory which was probable, one would think that those who otherwise objected to the facticity of the resurrection would be able to agree on that theory. However, the pint being stressed here is not so much that the liberal scholars could not agree on any one theory, but rather that the inherent weaknesses in each were pointed out. In other words, these scholars provide adequate refutations of each of the theories and thus revealed that they were not capable of accounting for the facts.

22. Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., pp. 38, 42 for example.

23. Ibid., pp. 41-43. R. Lofton Hudson reaches a similar conclusion concerning Jesus’ being alive in the preaching of the church. See R. Lofton Hudson, “What One Easter Meant to Me”, Christian Century, April 18, 1973, pp. 450-452, especially p. 451.

24. Marxsen, op.cit., p. 147.

25. Ibid., pp. 77, 110, 128, 141, 144.

26. Ibid., cf. pp. 128-129 with p. 147.

27. Marxsen does suggest just this (op.cit., pp. 144-145).

28. Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., p. 5 and Maier’s First Easter, op.cit., p. 115.

29. Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., p. 75, footnote number 128.

30. Ladd, op.cit., pp. 146-147.

31. Ibid., pp. 152-153, footnote number five.

32. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., especially p. 100.

33. At this point in the above quote, Ladd supplies a footnote in which he states his view that those who believe that Jesus is still alive but who insist that he did not rise bodily from the tomb are voicing all illogical opinion. Jesus either arose or he is dead (Ladd, op.cit., pp. 152-153, footnote number 5).

34. Ibid., pp. 145-146.

35. Machen notes that this interpretation was also prevalent in the older liberalism of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries (op.cit., pp. 108-109).

36. Such theories would of course be rejected regardless of whether a theologian, historian, philosopher or other such scholar formulated the hypotheses. The field of specialty makes no difference here, as the alternative theory would still be forced to answer the same objections as were raised above.

Chapter 12

1. See Blaikie, op.cit., pp. 122-136 and Montgomery’s History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 87-89 and Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 115-116.

2. Barth makes this claim, for instance, in his Church Dogmatic, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 335-336.

3. For the reasoning for these first two criticisms, see chapter four above.

4. The logical steps for these three criticisms of Kierkegaard cannot be completely ascertained from this brief summary. See chapter seven for an in-depth study of this critique.

5. These four criticisms of Barth were later altered in chapter eight so that they also applied to the scholars who followed him.

6. For example, see I Corinthians 15:4-8, especially verse 6; Luke 34:36-43; John 20:24-28; Acts 1:3; 10:40-41. Christian doctrines are also said to be true because of the resurrection (see Acts 17:30-31; Romans 1:4).

7. As with Kierkegaard, the reasons for these four criticisms cannot be fully gleaned from this brief survey. See especially chapter eight for the rationale here.

8. This was the result of the logical study of faith and reason in chapter four.

9. For Kierkegaard’s view, see especially Attack Upon “Christendom”, op.cit., pp. 149, 210, 280, 287; cf. Heinecken’s Soren Kierkegaard”, In Marty and Peerman, op.cit., pp. 131, 133, 134. For Barth’s view, see in particular his Church Dogmatics, op.cit., vol. IV, part 1, pp. 248-254.

Chapter 13

1. Ladd’s conception of the resurrection occurring in history does differ somewhat from the others, and this has already been considered above. All four scholars agree that this event is the best explanation of the historical facts and thus they also agree in accepting it as the most probable conclusion.

2. The significance of this criticism against all four of these scholars will be more fully explained in the last chapter.

3. See, for example, Pannenberg, Revelation as History, op.cit., p. 147 and Maier, First Easter, op.cit., p. 120.

Chapter 14

1. See Montgomery, History and Christianity, op.cit., pp. 88-89 and Where is History Going?, op.cit., pp. 115-116; Blaikie, op.cit., p. 135; Daniel Fuller, op.cit., p. 188; Ladd, op.cit., pp. 12-13; Maier, “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., p. 5.

2. There are very few (if any) reputable theologians today who doubt that Jesus actually died on the cross.

3. Ladd adds here the historicity of the account of the graveclothes being found in the empty tomb (op.cit., p. 94), since the description of them bears the marks of eyewitness testimony.

4. For similar lists, see Ladd, Ibid., pp. 13, 91-94, 132-133.

5. We will return to a final evaluation of these alternate theories later.

6. Ladd, op.cit., pp. 27, 140-141, in reference to Helmut Thielicke’s name for this evidence.

7. As was shown earlier, even those who do not accept overly objective appearances of Jesus often accept the belief in the empty tomb. See Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 48-49, 69-70, 179-180 and Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., pp. 100-104.

8. When speaking with an “agnostic” on the subject of Jesus’ resurrection a few years ago, this writes was told that the stance taken by the Jewish leaders in the body of Acts was the strongest demonstration of the reality of this event.

9. See Acts 1:21, 22; 2:24, 32; 3:15, 26; 4:10; 530, etc.

10. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 242-250.

11. “Positive” evidence is a reference to events which point directly to the resurrection, while “negative” evidence is that which is received from refuting the naturalistic theories. Of course, both are positive as far as the reality of the resurrection is concerned.

12. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., pp. 188-261.

13. Maier, First Easter, op.cit., pp. 114-112 and “The Empty Tomb as History”, op.cit., pp. 4-6.

14. Carl Braaten, History and Hermeneutics, Volume II of New Directions in Theology Today, edited by William Horden (Seven volumes; Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1966) p. 78.

15. Reginald Fuller, op.cit., p. 48.

16. Ramm, Protestant Christian Evidences, op.cit., p. 194.

17. Wand, op.cit., p. 122.

18. Even critical theology accepts this belief on the part of the disciples. For instance, see Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology” in Kerygma and Myth, op.cit., p. 42.

19. Other naturalistic theories refuted here in addition to these three include the objective vision theory (including the telegram theory), the hypothesis of the continuing spiritual presence of Jesus’ personality in his disciples’ minds, and the fraud theory (including the stolen body hypothesis). See especially chapter six for these refutations.

20. Pannenberg, Jesus—God and Man, op.cit., pp. 88-106.

21. Daniel Fuller, op.cit., see pp. 38-39, 45-49, 67-68 for examples of this.

22. Ladd, op.cit., pp. 132-142.

23. Maier, First Easter, op.cit., pp. 105-113.

24. See Morison’s book Who Moved the Stone?, op.cit., especially the Preface and pp. 9-12; cf. pp. 86-102 for instance. The first chapter appropriately tells of the original book that could not be written against the resurrection and life of Jesus because of the facts.

25. This work was reprinted in 1965 (Grand Rapids: Baker Book House).

26. See Josh McDowell, Evidence that Demands A Verdict (San Bernardino: Published by Campus Crusade for Christ International, no date), especially pp. 199-200. See also the tape by McDowell distributed by this same organization, entitled “Resurrection: Fact of Fallacy?”

27. Viggo Olsen, The Agnostic Who Dared to Search (Chicago: Mood Press, 1974). For Olsen’s discussion of the resurrection, see pp. 36-37, 39, 46-47 of this booklet.

28. Stott records a letter written by Clarke with the above affirmations. See John R.W. Stott, Basic Christianity (Chicago: Inter-Varsity Press, 1965), p. 46.

29. McDowell, op.cit., pp. 196-202.

30. See Reginald Fuller, op.cit., pp. 37, 177-178; Raymond Brown, The Virginal Conception and Bodily Resurrection of Jesus, op.cit., p. 94, footnote number 160 and p. 95; Ladd, op.cit., pp. 104-106 for a few examples of this belief.

31. William Hamilton, The New Essence of Christianity (New York: Association Press, 1961), p. 116, note.

32. John A.T. Robinson, Exploration Into God (Stanford University Press, 1967), p. 113.

33. Wand, op.cit., pp. 93-94.

34. Ibid., pp. 30, 51-52, 70-71, 101.

35. Even secular theologian William Hamilton oppose the contemporary view which gives existential importance to the concept that Jesus is alive but denies that he literally rose from the dead. Hamilton also asserts that without the historical event of the resurrection, Christian faith loses all meaning (op.cit., p. 116, note). Here he perceives the case quite well.

 

 

Copyright ©2010 by Dr. Gary R. Habermas. All rights reserved. Return To Top >>